1. Introduction
In mathematics, the Riemann hypothesis is a conjecture that the Riemann zeta function has its zeros only at the negative even integers and complex numbers with real part
. As usual
is the sum-of-divisors function of
n:
where
means the integer
d divides
n. Define
to be
. We say that
holds provided that
The constant
is the Euler-Mascheroni constant and log is the natural logarithm. An upper bound for
can be derived from its multiplicity:
Proposition 1.1.
For ([4] (2.7) pp. 362):
The following inequality is based on natural logarithms:
The Chebyshev function
is given by
where
means all the prime numbers
p that are less than or equal to
x. It is known that
Proposition 1.3.
For ([3] Lemma 2.7 (4) pp. 19):
Proposition 1.4.
For ([3] [Lemma 2.7 (5) pp. 19]):
Proposition 1.5.
For ([8] [Corollary 1 (3.30) pp. 70]):
The Ramanujan’s Theorem states that if the Riemann hypothesis is true, then
holds for large enough
n [
6]. Next, we have the Robin’s Theorem:
Proposition 1.6. holds for all natural numbers if and only if the Riemann hypothesis is true [7] [Theorem 1 pp. 188].
In 1997, Ramanujan’s old notes were published where it was defined the generalized highly composite numbers, which include the superabundant and colossally abundant numbers [
6]. These numbers were also studied by Leonidas Alaoglu and Paul Erdos (1944) [
2]. Let
denote the first
m consecutive primes, then an integer of the form
with
is called an Hardy-Ramanujan integer [
4] [pp. 367]. A natural number
n is called superabundant precisely when, for all natural numbers
Proposition 1.7. If n is superabundant, then n is a Hardy-Ramanujan integer [2] [Theorem 1 pp. 450].
Several analogues of the Riemann hypothesis have already been proved. Many authors expect (or at least hope) that it is true. However, there are some implications in case of the Riemann hypothesis could be false.
Proposition 1.8. If is the smallest integer such that does not hold, then n must be a superabundant number [1] [Theorem 3 pp. 273].
Proposition 1.9. If is the smallest integer such that does not hold, then where q is the largest prime factor of n [4] [Lemma 6.1 pp. 369].
Proposition 1.10. If is the smallest integer such that does not hold, then where q is the largest prime factor of n [9] [Theorem 4.2 pp. 748].
By combining these results, we present a proof of the Riemann hypothesis.
2. Main Result
Definition 2.1. For every prime number
, we define the sequence
The following is a key Lemma.
Lemma 2.2.
Let denote the first m consecutive primes such that and . Then
Proof. By Proposition 1.3, we know that
In this way, we can show that
We notice that
Consequently, we obtain that
By Proposition 1.4, we can prove that
when
. □
This is the main insight.
Lemma 2.3. If is the smallest integer such that does not hold, then , and , where is the primorial number of order m and .
Proof. By Propositions 1.7 and 1.8, the primes
must be the first
m consecutive primes and
. In addition, we know that
by Proposition 1.10. If
is the smallest integer such that
does not hold, then we deduce that
and
by Proposition 1.1. In addition, we know that
for all
by Lemma 2.2 since
. As result, we obtain that
since
by transitivity. By Proposition 1.1 and 1.5, we can see that
under the assumption that
does not hold. This implies that
We claim that
under the assumption that
does not hold. Certainly, if we assume that
then we would have
where this implies that
which is a trivial contradiction according to the Proposition 1.7. By Proposition 1.4, we can infer from (
1) the following result:
which directly implies that
Therefore, the proof is done. □
This is the main Theorem.
Theorem 2.4. The Riemann hypothesis is true.
Proof. We will proceed by contradiction. Assume that
is the smallest integer such that
does not hold. By Propositions 1.7 and 1.8, the primes
must be the first
m consecutive primes and
. By Proposition 1.10, this also implies that
. By Lemma 2.3, we deduce that
which is the same as
after of applying the logarithm and distributing the terms. Certainly, we get this inequaltiy following the next steps:
First, we obtain after of applying the logarithm to the both sides.
Next, we get when we distribute the terms.
Finally, we arrive at if we apply the logarithm to the both sides once again.
That is equivalent to
after dividing both sides by
and under the assumption that
since
by Proposition 1.9. By Proposition 1.2, we obtain that
for all
. So, we would have
for all
. We arrive at:
after of applying the logarithm. That would be
which is
and
after of multiplying both sides by
and applying the exponentiation. By Lemma 2.3, we can further deduce that
where
Furthermore, we can infer that
where
Putting all together yields the following inequality:
which is
Hence, it is enough to show that
does not hold for all
since
Thus our original assumption that
does not hold has led to a final contradiction. By reductio ad absurdum, we prove that the Riemann hypothesis is true by Proposition 1.6. □
References
- Amir Akbary and Zachary Friggstad. Superabundant numbers and the Riemann hypothesis. The American Mathematical Monthly, 116(3):273–275, 2009. [CrossRef]
- Leonidas Alaoglu and Paul Erdos. On Highly Composite and Similar Numbers. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 56(3):448–469, 1944. [CrossRef]
- Safia Aoudjit, Djamel Berkane, and Pierre Dusart. On Robin’s criterion for the Riemann Hypothesis. Notes on Number Theory and Discrete Mathematics, 27(4):15–24, 2021. [CrossRef]
- YoungJu Choie, Nicolas Lichiardopol, Pieter Moree, and Patrick Solé. On Robin’s criterion for the Riemann hypothesis. Journal de Théorie des Nombres de Bordeaux, 19(2):357–372, 2007. [CrossRef]
- Jean-Louis Nicolas. The sum of divisors function and the Riemann hypothesis. The Ramanujan Journal, 58:1113–1157, 2022. [CrossRef]
- Jean-Louis Nicolas and Guy Robin. Highly Composite Numbers by Srinivasa Ramanujan. The Ramanujan Journal, 1(2):119–153, 1997. [CrossRef]
- Guy Robin. Grandes valeurs de la fonction somme des diviseurs et hypothèse de Riemann. J. Math. pures appl, 63(2):187–213, 1984.
- J. Barkley Rosser and Lowell Schoenfeld. Approximate Formulas for Some Functions of Prime Numbers. Illinois Journal of Mathematics, 6(1):64–94, 1962. [CrossRef]
- Frank Vega. Robin’s criterion on divisibility. The Ramanujan Journal, 59(3):745–755, 2022. [CrossRef]
|
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).