1. Introduction
Fermat’s Last Theorem, first stated by its namesake Pierre de Fermat in the
century, it claims that there are no positive integer solutions to the equation
, whenever
is greater than 2. In a margin note left on his copy of Diophantus’
Arithmetica, Fermat claimed that he had a proof which the margin was too small to contain [
1]. Later mathematicians such Leonhard Euler and Sophie Germain made significant contributions to its study [
2,
3], and
contributions by Ernst Kummer proved the theorem for a specific class of numbers [
4]. However, a complete solution remained out of reach.
Finally, in 1994, British mathematician Andrew Wiles announced a proof for Fermat’s Last Theorem. His work was complex and multifaceted, drawing on advance topics of mathematics such as elliptic curves, which were beyond the prevalent purview of knowledge during Fermat’s time. After some initial errors were addressed, Wiles’ work was hailed as the long-awaited proof of the Theorem [
5] and described as a “stunning advance” in the citation for Wiles’s Abel Prize award in 2016. It also proved much of the Taniyama-Shimura conjecture, subsequently known as the modularity theorem, and opened up entire new approaches to numerous other problems and mathematically powerful modularity lifting techniques [
6]. The techniques used by Wiles are ostensibly far from Fermat’s claimed proof in terms of extension, complexity and novelty of tools used−many of which were only available during the
century.
In this article, we present what we contend is a correct and short proof for Fermat’s Last Theorem. The degree of actual closeness it might have with Fermat’s own can only be speculated upon, but in our view simplicity was of paramount importance and we have deliberately eschewed techniques and results that were not available in the
century. The techniques developed here show promise for application to similar Diophantine equations and other problems in Number Theory such as the Beal conjecture, a well-known generalization of Fermat’s Last Theorem [
7].
2. Background and Ancillary Results
Definition 2.1. As usual,
stands for
integer d divides integer n; and we denote by
, the
greatest common divisor of
[
8].
Proposition 2.2 ([
9]).
Let greater than 1. If are coprime and , then .
Proposition 2.3 ([
9]).
Fermat’s little theorem states that if p is a prime number, then for any integer a, the following condition holds. In addition, if p does not divide a, then holds as well.
Proposition 2.4.
If n is a positive integer, then
3. Main Result
Theorem 3.1. The statement of Fermat’s Last Theorem is true.
Proof. We will proceed by contradiction. Aside from the fact that case was proven to have no solutions by Fermat himself, further simplifying assumptions at our disposal are:
the consideration of an odd prime p as the selected exponent;
the coprimality of ;
and the condition
on account of Catalan’s conjecture, proven by Mihăilescu in [
10].
Therefore, the Diophantine equation whose positive integer solvability constitutes our hypothesis is, for a given fixed prime
,
Assume such
exist.
-
Case 1:
-
Suppose that
are pairwise coprime with
p. Using the Proposition 2.3 we notice that
First we start with an equivalent expression of (
1)
Substituting
,
and using that
p is odd,
by Proposition 2.4. That is equivalent to
So, we would have
from (
3). If the prime number
p divides
, then
and thus,
a is divisible by
p. If
p does not divide
a, then this implies
according to Proposition 2.2 and properties of (
2). However, we can see that
We know that
by Proposition 2.3 since
p and
are pairwise coprime. Consequently, we obtain that (
) or (
or
) by Proposition 2.2. It is not possible that (
or
) whenever
p and
are pairwise coprime and therefore, it would be necessary that (
). In virtue of (
3), we would have
which is
By Proposition 2.3 and (
2), we can further deduce that
a is divisible by
p because
p would divide
when:
Since are pairwise coprime with p, we reach a contradiction.
-
Case 2:
-
Suppose that
are pairwise coprime with
p and
a is divisible by
p. By Proposition 2.3, we can see that
Substituting
,
and using that
p is odd,
by Proposition 2.4. That would be
After that, we check
from (
8). If the prime number
p divides
, then
and thus,
c is divisible by
p. If
p does not divide
c, then this implies
according to Proposition 2.2 and properties of (
7). Nevertheless, we can see that
We know that
by Proposition 2.3 since
and
p and
b are pairwise coprime. Consequently, we obtain that
Hence, it is enough to show that
for
. Since
, then we can further deduce that
b is divisible by
p due to
. Since
are pairwise coprime with
p, we reach a contradiction.
-
Case 3:
Suppose that
are pairwise coprime with
p and
b is divisible by
p. Following the same steps as the above case,
mutatis mutandis, and exploiting the symmetry of the left-hand side of (
1) with respect to
a and
b, we get another contradiction.
-
Case 4:
-
Suppose that
are pairwise coprime with
p and
c is divisible by
p. Using the Proposition 2.3 we can verify that
Now we continue with an equivalent expression of (
1)
Substituting
,
and using that
p is odd,
by Proposition 2.4. That is equivalent to
Thus, we would get
from (
10). If the prime number
p divides
, then
and thus,
b is divisible by
p. If
p does not divide
b, then this implies
according to Proposition 2.2 and properties of (
9). Besides, we can infer that
It is known that
by Proposition 2.3 since
and
p and
a are pairwise coprime. As result, this implies that
We only need to show that
for
. Since
, then we can confirm that
a is divisible by
p due to
. Since
are pairwise coprime with
p, we reach a contradiction.
-
Case 5:
Finally, we arrive at the following conclusion: Natural numbers
share
p as a common prime factor. However, this poses a contradiction with the pairwise coprimality of
assumed from the outset in (
1).
Thus our original assumption that (
1) had positive integer solutions for prime
has led to a final contradiction. □
4. Conclusion
This paper introduces a novel and concise proof of Fermat’s Last Theorem, a celebrated problem in number theory that has remained unsolved for centuries. We have demonstrated that the equation
has no positive integer solutions for any natural numbers
and any integer exponent
n greater than 2.
Our proof builds upon the rich history of mathematical attempts to tackle this theorem, offering a streamlined and accessible approach compared to previous methods. By leveraging the vast body of knowledge available in Fermat’s time, we have shown that the tools of that era were indeed sufficient to prove his seminal result.
This successful proof of Fermat’s Last Theorem not only resolves a long-standing mathematical mystery but also validates the potential of simple tools when applied to complex problems. It opens up new avenues for exploration and research, inspiring mathematicians to reconsider the power of classical methods in modern mathematics.
Acknowledgments
Many thanks to Sergi Simon for his support.
References
- Fermat, P.d. Oeuvres de Pierre de Fermat; Vol. 1, Gauthier-Villars, 1891.
- Euler, L. Elements of Algebra; Springer Science & Business Media, 2012. [CrossRef]
- Germain, S. Oeuvres philosophiques de Sophie Germain; Collection XIX, 2016.
- Kummer, E.E. Zur Theorie der complexen Zahlen 1847. [CrossRef]
- Wiles, A. Modular elliptic curves and Fermat’s Last Theorem. Annals of mathematics 1995, 141, 443–551. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ribet, K.A. Galois representations and modular forms. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 1995, 32, 375–402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Beal, A. A Generalization of Fermat’s Last Theorem: The Beal Conjecture and Prize Problem. Notices of the AMS 1997, 44. [Google Scholar]
- Abramowitz, M.; Stegun, I.A. Handbook of Mathematical Functions with Formulas, Graphs, and Mathematical Tables; Vol. 55, US Government printing office, 1968.
- Hardy, G.H.; Wright, E.M. An Introduction to the Theory of Numbers; Oxford University Press, 1979.
- Mihăilescu, P. Primary cyclotomic units and a proof of Catalans conjecture. J. Reine Angew. Math 2004, 572, 167–195. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
|
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).