The potential of RNA-based measurements are potentially applicable through a wide array of medical areas, e.g.
, diagnosing diseases, prognosis and therapeutic selection. Currently, among the most promising clinical applications, it is worth mentioning not only cancer research [
105], but also infectious diseases, transplant medicine and fetal monitoring [
106]. RNA sequencing (RNA-seq) has enabled us to detect a remarkably wide host of RNA species, such as mRNA, non-coding RNA, pathogen RNA, chimeric gene fusions, transcript isoforms and splice variants. RNS-seq has also led to the possibility of quantifying known, pre-defined RNA species and rare RNA transcript variants. Not only can differential expression and detection of novel transcripts be feasible, but so can the detection of mutations and germline variation be achieved through RNA-seq, possibly involving hundreds to thousands of expressed genetic variants, which enhances our ability to evaluate allele-specific expression of these variants. Since the mechanisms governing RNA for diagnostics and therapeutics were first discovered and explored in the late 1990s, RNA interference (RNAi, a mechanism for gene silencing underpinned by short interfering RNAs, siRNA, and discovered in 1997 by Mello) [
107,
108] therapeutics has been developing remarkably fast, and our understanding of such highly complex processes and interactions has deepened considerably ever since [
109]. Clinical trials have already begun. Still, such therapies relying on “gene-silencing” are even more controversial than diagnostic applications, since they may be viewed as akin to gene-editing/genetic engineering. It has been literally decades that such techniques have been developing and eliciting spirited debates among scientists, bioethicists, policy- and law-makers centered around how to best harness the potential of such breakthroughs to the benefit of potentially billions of human beings [
110]. The hope and dream that diseases could one day be vanquished through the deliberate and targeted manipulation or editing of genes are the driving force behind the Human Genome Project [
111,
112], through which the complete human DNA sequence was first outlined and mapped in 2003. Such a fundamental principle at the core of which lies disease treatment via genetic modification dates back to the 1960s, i.e.
, when it was first observed that viral DNA had the ability to trigger cellular modulation during an infection. Early efforts aimed at gene modification date back to the 1970s [
113,
114]; recombinant DNAs (rDNAs) was used for that purpose, i.e.
, a combination of more than one DNA sequence from one or more species. Primary transfection methods were viral infection or calcium phosphate. Such innovations gradually bore fruit in the form of cell line development, genetically modified animals and even the creation of human proteins such as insulin in bacteria [
115]. By the late 1970s, messenger RNA (mRNA) in vitro had been transfected by liposomes; this gave rise to rabbit globin expressed in mouse lymphocytes [
116]. mRNA sequences in the cell cytoplasm, in order to inhibit protein translation or to induce exon skipping were targeted by newly developed antisense oligonucleotides (ASOs) [
117]. Not surprisingly, it was back then that such fast-moving progress ignited a broad-ranging discourse encompassing genetic engineering in terms of its ethical, social, political and even economic implications. As a result, regulations limiting the different “tiers” of gene-editing were drafted and enacted. Later major developments are constituted by zinc finger nuclease (ZFN) to cleave a target DNA and two decades later TALEN and CRISPR/Cas9. Hence, it stands to reason that before such novel and potentially revolutionary therapeutic approaches can become mainstream from the standpoint of clinical applications, it is of utmost importance to discuss the legal and ethical issues arising from their use [
118]. An analysis of the ethically relevant features of RNAi therapies is therefore essential for the purpose of producing a comprehensive risk-benefit analysis. Ethically relevant traits such as siRNA delivery and the specificity of silencing effects cannot be brushed aside. Furthermore, the future development of RNAi-based therapeutic options ought to take into account and respect patient autonomy by considering the risks of generating infection-competent viruses or possibly introducing genetic changes in germ line cells. Just as importantly, issues relative to justice in care delivery, such as equal access as opposed to private acquisition, and the right to participate in clinical trials should also be prioritized. The sheer scale of progress made in ncRNA research applied to cancer, and our ever-greater understanding of tumor biology, which will lay the groundwork for the development of new ‘smart’ drugs tailored to a patient-oriented approach, is poised to enable us to minimize adverse side effects and improving the patient prospects for recovery [
119]. Having said that, the risk which needs confronting is that innovative biomedical techniques may outpace our ethical, legal and regulatory frameworks, leading to “grey areas” similar to those found in genome editing research and artificial intelligence. In addition, assisted reproductive technologies and fertility preservation also pose complex and challenging issues from the ethics and legal perspectives. Fertility preservation should only be offered to patients with endometrial cancer stage Ia grade 1 (G1), who present without myometrial invasion or where the cancer has invaded less than 50% of the myometrium, with no evidence of pathological lymph nodes or no evidence of synchronous or metachronous ovarian tumor [
16]. The most common fertility-sparing treatment for endometrial cancer is hormonal therapy with progestins, which can induce regression or stabilization of the tumor. However, this treatment has several limitations, such as low response rate, high recurrence rate, lack of standardization, and potential adverse effects on the fetus. Therefore, patients who opt for fertility preservation should be carefully selected and counseled about the risks and benefits of this approach. They should also be monitored closely during and after the treatment and advised to undergo definitive surgery after completing their childbearing. ART can offer an alternative or complementary option for women who want to conceive after being treated for endometrial cancer. However, ART also poses some ethical dilemmas, such as the safety and efficacy of the procedures, the potential harm to the mother and the child, the disposal or donation of surplus embryos [
120], and the access and affordability of the services [
121,
122]. Moreover, some ART techniques involve genetic testing or manipulation of the embryos, which raise further ethical questions about the respect for human dignity, autonomy, and diversity [
123,
124]. Undoubtedly, ART can provide hope and opportunity for women who want to have children after being diagnosed with EC. However, ART also involves medical, legal, and ethical challenges that require careful consideration and multidisciplinary collaboration. Therefore, patients who are interested in ART should be informed and supported by a team of experts who can help them make informed decisions that are consistent with their values and preferences [
125].