Preprint
Article

A Maximum Entropy Resolution to the Wine/Water Paradox

Altmetrics

Downloads

125

Views

39

Comments

0

A peer-reviewed article of this preprint also exists.

This version is not peer-reviewed

Submitted:

20 June 2023

Posted:

21 June 2023

You are already at the latest version

Alerts
Abstract
The Principle of Indifference (“PI”: the simplest non-informative prior in Bayesian probability) has been shown to lead to paradoxes since Bertrand (1889). Von Mises (1928) introduced the “Wine/Water Paradox” as a resonant example of a “Bertrand paradox”, and which has been presented as demonstrating that the PI must be rejected. We now resolve these paradoxes by a Maximum Entropy (MaxEnt) treatment of the PI that also includes information provided by Benford’s “Law of Anomalous Numbers” (1938). We show that the PI should be understood to represent a family of informationally-identical MaxEnt solutions; each solution being identified with its own explicitly justified boundary condition. In particular, our solution of the Wine/Water Paradox exploits Benford’s Law to construct a non-uniform distribution representing the universal constraint of scale invariance, which is a physical consequence of the Second Law of Thermodynamics.
Keywords: 
Subject: Physical Sciences  -   Thermodynamics

Introduction

Benford’s Law [1] is the peculiar observation that in many real-life sets of numerical data, the leading digit is likely to be small. It was first observed by Simon Newcomb in 1881 [2], who commented: “That the ten digits do not occur with equal frequency must be evident to anyone making much use of logarithm tables, and noticing how much faster the first pages wear out than the last ones”. Although this is an expected statistical phenomenon [3], the reasons for it are remarkably obscure and there remain a number of open problems [4]. Benford’s Law has since generated significant interest, including treatments that highlight its connections with entropy: Iafrate et al. (2015) [5] showed that the Law is derivable from a statistical mechanics treatment, with Don Lemons (2019) [6] extending their treatment to explicitly show the connection with thermodynamics.
It has become clear that Benford’s Law is associated with scale invariance, although Berger & Hill [4] give a simple counterexample for the (false) statement that “To be Benford, a random variable or dataset needs to cover at least several orders of magnitude”. Nevertheless, since we have demonstrated the validity of Quantitative Geometrical Thermodynamics (QGT) with an Euler-Lagrange variational calculus framework underpinning its Maximum Entropy (MaxEnt) approach to hyperbolic systems ranging over 35 orders of magnitude [7] (or more [8]), we expect such scale invariance to be present whenever the Second Law of Thermodynamics is at work. And we therefore also expect Benford’s Law with its logarithmic character to be ubiquitous (consistent with the fundamental and universal character of the Second Law) and indeed a “proxy” for the Second Law complete with all the entailed physical limitations and constraints.
The Principle of Indifference (PI) is the simplest non-informative prior in Bayesian probability, mandating that, in the absence of any relevant evidence to the contrary, all possible outcomes should be treated as equally probable. “The Principle of Indifference is a symmetry principle stating [that] logical symmetries should be reflected, in the absence of any discriminating information, in uniform a priori probability distributions” (Howson & Urbach, 2006 [9]).
However, Joseph Bertrand showed in 1889 [10] that the PI leads to apparent paradoxes for problems which have infinite sets of possible outcomes. Nicholas Shackel (2007) [11] analysed Bertrand’s Paradox (including Jaynes’ treatment of it [12]) concluding that in such cases it continues to refute the PI. Of course, the first of the “plague of infinities” of the PI is introduced at the outset, since a uniform probability distribution entails a MaxEnt distribution characterised by an infinite temperature (since temperature is inversely proportional to the Lagrange multiplier of the MaxEnt formulation: see Discussion below).
The Wine/Water Paradox was introduced by Von Mises (1928) [13] as a resonant example of a “Bertrand paradox”, and has recently been re-analysed by Mikkelson [14] who concludes that the paradox is resolved if the symmetries of the problem are taken properly into account.
Briefly, an instance of the “Wine/Water Paradox” is given by Mikkelson [14] as:
There is a certain quantity of liquid. All that we know about the liquid is that it is composed entirely of water and wine, and that the ratio of wine:water (w) is between ⅓ and 3. So ⅓ ≤ w ≤ 3. Now, what is the probability that w ≤ 2?
Different ways of stating the Principle of Indifference give different answers to this question, and so the Wine/Water Paradox apparently represents an important counterexample to the PI, playing “a curiously pivotal role in this discussion. Everyone seems to agree [that the Wine/Water Paradox] has no solution [and therefore that the PI] has fallen into serious disrepute among probability theorists” [14], even suggesting “that the principle of indifference must be totally rejected” (Jaynes 1973 [12]; although he also says: “the principle of indifference has been unjustly maligned in the past; what is needed was not blanket condemnation, but recognition of the proper way to apply it”). Bas van Fraassen also thinks there is a fundamental failure of the PI: “Probability is not uniquely assignable on the basis of a Principle of Indifference” [15].
In the language of Bayesian analysis, if a problem definition is to be considered complete and self-consistent then it requires a complete specification of the prior information as well as the data, such that logical analysis from different points of view should lead to exactly the same solution.
Howson & Urbach [9] have stated that the PI “is a symmetry principle”, and associated with this property is Jaynes’ [12] idea of transformation group theory being applied to statistical problems invoking the PI; in particular, the assumption that changing the parameters (including the scale) of a problem should not change the state of knowledge. Such symmetry principles underlies both Special and General Relativity, where the hyperbolic rotations associated with Minkowski space-time form such a transformation group.
There are curious parallels with the statistical mechanical calculation of the thermodynamic entropy of a physical system, which depends on the granularity chosen to analyse the system under consideration. Elements of the system smaller than the graining represent the microstates of the system, which can be ignored since their permutations do not change the value of the entropy calculated. It is the macrostates of the system that represent the observational structure of the system.
In any case, when discussing ignorance of a system, it is the Principle of Maximum Entropy (MaxEnt) that is important, particularly when a system is considered to be underdetermined. From a thermodynamical perspective this is equivalent to the associated Lagrange multipliers being assigned a value of zero, which should be recognised as equivalent to assuming an infinite system temperature (as briefly mentioned above and elaborated in the Discussion below). Such an assumption is both unphysical and also unjustified per se on informational grounds (since if we are completely ignorant of the temperature we cannot assume any definite value). The MaxEnt principle is applied to systems associated with the minimum of information. Howson & Urbach [9] make a clear statement to this effect: "Jaynes's [MaxEnt treatment] appeals...to the criterion...of minimum information: ...the least information... or... the fewest assumptions..." As Jaynes himself puts it: “How do we find the prior representing ‘complete ignorance’? ... the maximum entropy principle will lead to a definite, parameter-independent method of setting up prior distributions [such that] we express complete ignorance by assigning a uniform prior probability density” [12].
We regard this unjustified implicit assumption of infinite system temperature as being at the root of the disrepute of the PI and intend to approach the problem rather differently, invoking Benford’s Law as an explicit “proxy” for a more physical application of the Second Law allowing the relevant MaxEnt parameters (including the Lagrange multiplier, but see Discussion) to be properly determined and entailing physically consistent solutions.
It is interesting that Benford’s Law has not (to our knowledge) yet been applied to this class of problems. It is curious that Jaynes, who did so much to propose and support the principle of Maximum Entropy neither saw the contradiction of effectively employing a specific (infinite) temperature for the assumption of a uniform prior probability density, nor exploited Benford’s Law (which he was clearly aware of, citing it multiple times in his book on probability theory [16]).

Resolution of the Wine/Water Paradox

We want to know what is the median ratio W of the wine:water volume ratios v/u, v′/u′ (choosing two representative ratios from the distribution), where for convenience (and without any loss of generality) we assume v, v′, u and u′ are appropriately integer quantities, such that there’s an equal probability of the wine:water ratios being above and below that median point. The key issue here is that an equivalent answer must be obtained for the symmetrical problem expressed using the inverse water:wine ratios, u/v and u′/v′. For convenience we assume v′/u′> v/u but of course, the inverse (symmetrical) assumption v′/u′< v/u may also be made. The wine:water ratio w can therefore be placed between the limits:
v/u ≤ w ≤ v′/u′
If the original statement of the problem does not employ integer values in Equation (1a) for the limits of w (such as in Mikkelson’s example), then it can be transformed by multiplying by a common factor so that the limits are integers. Multiplying the wine:water ratio w by uu′, so as to define a transformed variable x=wuu′, then the limits of the scaled variable x (which now no longer represents a ratio quantity) are given by:
u′v ≤ x ≤ uv′
For any number system of base B, Benford’s Law states that the leading digit N for any number represented in that base B has a relative probability p(N) of occurrence of:
p ( N ) = log B ( 1 + 1 N )
Since we also need to analyse the reciprocal quantities we choose our base B as the product:
B = u + 1 u + 1 v + 1 v + 1
The limit quantities P≡uv and Q≡uv′ (seen, in effect, in Equation (1b)) may be taken without any loss of generality to be, respectively, their own leading digit representation in the base B, so that by Benford’s law the natural probabilities of occurrence of P and Q are:
p ( P ) = log B ( 1 + 1 P )
p ( Q ) = log B ( 1 + 1 Q )
We can immediately write the ratio of these two probabilities as:
p ( P ) p ( Q ) = log B ( 1 + 1 / P ) log B ( 1 + 1 / Q ) = ln ( 1 + 1 / P ) ln ( 1 + 1 / Q )
where for convenience we employ the natural logarithm. The most basic MaxEnt distribution (that is, the probability distribution with the fewest possible extraneous assumptions or constraints) is the negative exponential distribution so that the MaxEnt probability distribution for the scaled variable x is:
p(x)=Aexp(−λx)
where λ is indistinguishable from a Lagrange multiplier. That is to say, the parameter λ can be considered here to represent the physical constraint of scale invariance that has been introduced into the problem formulation by the ubiquitous influence of the Second Law of Thermodynamics. For x lying between the two numbers P and Q (as per Equation (1b)):
P Q A e λ x d x = 1
hence:
A = λ e λ P e λ Q
It is clear that the MaxEnt distribution Aexp(-λx) is underdetermined since it has two variables, A and λ, but only one constraint (Equation (5b)). This under-determination for Aexp(-λx) can be thought to have generated the Wine/Water Paradox, since a unique designation for each of A and λ was not available. But, asserting Benford’s Law and recasting Equation (4) with the help of Equation (5a):
p ( P ) p ( Q ) = exp ( λ P ) exp ( λ Q ) = ln ( 1 + 1 / P ) ln ( 1 + 1 / Q )
Thus Equation (6) represents a new independent relation allowing for the unique determination of the exponential parameter λ, and thence the most likely (MaxEnt) distribution for the parameter x, since Equation (5c) can then be used to uniquely determine A. Note that it’s clear that λ≠0 unless P=Q; that is to say, only the trivial case (and, in effect, a null Wine/Water proposition) leads to what might be considered the uniform probability distribution (with λ=0) conventionally associated with the PI.
Thus, the initial aspect of von Mises’ conundrum can now be straightforwardly solved; that is to say, the value for the median probability is given by the value x=X, where X (with P X Q ) is uniquely determined by the condition:
P X A e λ x d x = X Q A e λ x d x = 1 2
using the LHS of Equation (7a) leads to a closed solution for X:
X = 1 λ ln ( e λ P λ 2 A )
Transforming back into the ratio w, leads to a median wine:water ratio given by W=X/uu′:
W = 1 u u λ ln e λ P λ 2 A
Considering now the reciprocal ratios, and in particular the reciprocal variable y (≡1/w), then the relative proportions of water and wine are now considered to be u/v and u′/v′, such that (for u/v> u′/v′) we have:
u′/v′ ≤ y ≤ u/v
Then, as before we may without any loss of generality multiply the appropriate relative inverse ratios u/v and u′/v′, by the factor vv′ so as to ensure integer quantities obeying Benford’s law as per Eqs.3, and thereby consider the scaled variable zvv′y, such that (assuming again a MaxEnt probability distribution for z) we have:
u′v ≤ z ≤ uv′
or indeed
PzQ
with:
p(z)=Cexp(−Λz)
With the resulting limit quantities P≡uv and Q≡uv′ still applying and the MaxEnt equation Equation (8d) equivalent to Equation (5a), it is also now clear that CA and Λ≡λ, such that it is also clear that the median point corresponds to the same equation Equation (7b). That is, the problem has the same solution (as required) as for its inverse (mutatis mutandis).

Discussion

In applying this theory to the Wine/Water Paradox using Mikkelson’s parameters (1≤ x ≤ 9, transferring to integer numbers simply by multiplying Mikkelson’s range by a factor 3) we now have the means to find the value of W such that there is an equal probability of the actual ratio being above or below W. The above analysis reveals that the solution to the Water-Wine Paradox is given by (solving Equation (6)):
λ=0.235481801
with the associated value for A given by:
A=0.35142409
The median value W is found from Equation (7c) to be:
W=1.11420745
This median value of the probability distribution represents the ratio of Wine/Water such that there is an equal probability of the actual ratio being above or below that value. As required, the inverse problem has the same median value.
It is of interest to note that the median probability point associated with W is not unity (that is, equal quantities of water and wine). This is an interesting aspect to the Wine/Water problem, that invites some comment. In particular, we note that in our integer terms of P and Q, then Mikkelson’s parameters are equivalent to the range lying between 1 and 9, with a mid-point of 3, corresponding to the ‘geometric’ mid-point. Clearly the general result that W be unity would in turn imply that the solution for W is the geometric mean, which is attractive since it appears scaleless. However, the geometric mean doesn’t actually conform to the logarithmic (hyperbolic) nature of the universe, as exemplified by the entropic basis of the Second Law (see Parker & Jeynes 2019 [17], Equation (1b)). Equation (1) shows that Benford’s Law is also “logarithmic” in the same way, which is why we called it a “proxy” for the Second Law. When considering the median probability from the perspective of physical quantities, the logarithmic calculation for W (as per Equation (7c)) is the more meaningful physical approach.
Although not exactly the same, the velocity addition rule of Special Relativity offers a related (hyperbolic) means to combine two velocities; similarly, the addition of optical Fresnel-based reflection amplitudes (with phase properties) for the overall probability amplitude of the reflection from a multilayer dielectric stack also follows a hyperbolic tangent (tanh) addition formalism (see Corzine et al. [18]); that is, neither a geometric nor an arithmetic addition in both these cases. As is well-known, the science of probability has always tended to defy intuition by offering unexpected and surprising solutions: the Monty Hall problem (see Enßlin et al. 2019 [19]; Enßlin & Westerkamp 2019 [20]) being just one example of many; while Edwin Jaynes also delighted in exploiting the Maximum Entropy machinery to objectively solve problems (such as the loaded dice, see Jaynes 1978 [21], Jaynes 1982 [22]) in a manner aimed at disconcerting those unfamiliar with these methods.
Jeffrey Mikkelson [14] considers that he has “dissolved” the Wine/Water paradox by “epistemically” distinguishing between “primary” and “derivative” facts. We have shown that explicitly invoking Benford’s Law yields a more clear cut (and satisfactory) resolution.
Marc Burock [23] doesn’t like Mikkelson’s solution since he regards it as silently introducing extra information. Instead, he draws attention to “the joint sample space of a ratio and its inverse” and claims that applying the PI to this space resolves the paradox. In our opinion this can be regarded as a sort of scale invariance which we implement explicitly using Benford’s Law.
For the question “What is the probability P* that w ≤ 2?”, we again multiply Mikkelson’s parameters by 3 and calculate the integrated probability for Px≤6, with P=1:
P * = P 6 A e λ x d x = A λ e λ x P 6 = A e λ P λ e 6 P λ 1 = 0.81595117
Michael Deakin’s is a sophisticated discussion [24] of both Mikkelson’s and Burock’s conclusions. He points out that Mikkelson finds P= 5/6=0.833 where Burock finds P= 0.764 (from Equation (10) above we find P= 0.816). He concludes that the problem as posed may have any solution in the interval ½ ≤ P≤ 1. We regard the problem as rather better-posed than he thinks it is, with a definite solution supplied by the extra information intrinsic to Benford’s Law.
John Norton comments, very plausibly: “If our initial ignorance is sufficiently great, there are so many ways to be indifferent that that the resulting equalities contradict the additivity of the probability calculus. We can properly assign equal probabilities in a prior probability distribution only if our ignorance is not complete and we know enough to be able to identify which is the right partition of the outcome space over which to exercise indifference” [25]. His is a paper on “probabilistic epistemology”, but here we prefer to avoid epistemological questions in favour of explicit physics (although it is not always possible to avoid metaphysics [26]).
We have above repeatedly alluded to the issue of Lagrange multipliers, an issue which highlights an apparently unphysical aspect to the most basic form of the Principle of Indifference (PI). The point here is that the Maximum Entropy method looks for stationary solutions of the system Lagrangian given the constraints, which constraints may be represented by the (constant scalar) “Lagrange multipliers”. It is a standard result (see for example Caticha 2008 [27] Eq.5.38) that, for the Boltzmann distribution, the Lagrange multiplier representing the energy conservation constraint is inversely proportional to the temperature; and our Equation (5a) features the parameter λ that is indistinguishable from such a Lagrange multiplier. It is also obvious that for uniform distributions (such as that generally implied by the PI: all such systems are necessarily the same, that is, the relevant probability distributions are independent of particular constraints), the Lagrange multipliers must be zero. This in turn implies an (unphysical) infinite system temperature. Here we draw attention to this problem, while using Benford’s Law to select one of the family of Maximum Entropy solutions, one with a parameter that is equivalent to a non-zero Lagrange multiplier. This problem has a solution not given by a uniformly distributed probability function, as one would intuitively expect from the PI. Perhaps this has been such a persistent Paradox precisely because the simplest form of the principle of indifference as applied to the Wine/Water paradox entails a trivial solution (P=Q) even though the probability functions of sensible solutions are not distributed uniformly, even as they remain MaxEnt solutions.

Conclusions

We have shown that the value of λ obtained explicitly (Equation (6)) resolves the Water/Wine paradox, being based on a more physically realistic expression of the Principle of Indifference, and which remains valid even when the problem is expressed in a different (but symmetrical) manner.
The “paradox” is one famous example of a class of paradoxes described by Bertrand, and its resolution here for one case is expected to resolve the other cases too mutatis mutandis.
We regard the “paradox” as appearing paradoxical because it is ostensibly underdetermined as stated, so that different solutions seem valid for an apparently well-posed problem. This underdetermination is an expression of unrecognised and unstated priors disturbing the analysis; while it is, of course, well-known that a correct Bayesian analysis must also correctly state all the prior knowledge of the system.
We solve the “paradox” by explicitly supplying the missing prior (in the form of Benford’s Law): namely, the condition of scale invariance. Other commentators have also noticed this prior but have treated it metaphysically. Here we treat it physically.
Our treatment shows that the Principle of Indifference does not necessarily imply a uniform probability distribution as one usually expects. This is because a uniform distribution implies a null Lagrange multiplier, which in turn implies an (unphysical) infinite system temperature. But note also that a null Lagrange multiplier also implies an independence of relevant constraints; this independence having been (illegitimately) smuggled in as a further (unacknowledged) implicit assumption. We have shown rigorously that the explicit assumption of scale invariance required by the Second Law and implemented using Benford’s Law allows a distinct and consistent Maximum Entropy solution to the Wine/Water problem with a non-zero Lagrange multiplier explicitly evaluated.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization: Michael Parker and Chris Jeynes; Formal analysis: Michael Parker; Methodology: Michael Parker; Writing – original draft: Michael Parker and Chris Jeynes; Writing – review & editing: Michael Parker and Chris Jeynes.

Funding

This research received no funding.

References

  1. Frank Benford. The law of anomalous numbers. Proc. Amer. Philosophical Soc., 78 (1938) 551–572. Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/984802.
  2. Simon Newcomb, Note on the frequency of use of the different digits in natural numbers, American Journal of Mathematics, 4 (1881) 39–40. [CrossRef]
  3. Theodore P. Hill, A Statistical Derivation of the Significant-Digit Law, Statist. Sci. 10 (1995) 354 – 363. [CrossRef]
  4. Arno Berger, Theodore P. Hill, The Mathematics of Benford’s Law - A Primer, Stat. Methods Appl. 30 (2020) 779–795. [CrossRef]
  5. Joseph R. Iafrate, Steven J. Miller, and Frederick W. Strauch, Equipartitions and a distribution for numbers: A statistical model for Benford's law, Phys. Rev. E 91 (2015) 062138. [CrossRef]
  6. Don S. Lemons, Thermodynamics of Benford's first digit law, American Journal of Physics 87 (2019) 787. [CrossRef]
  7. M.C.Parker, C.Jeynes, W.N.Catford, Halo Properties in Helium Nuclei from the Perspective of Geometrical Thermodynamics, Annalen der Physik 534 (2022) 2100278 (11pp); [CrossRef]
  8. M.C.Parker, C. M.C.Parker, C.Jeynes, Relating a system’s Hamiltonian to its Entropy Production using a Complex-Time approach, Entropy 25 (2023) 629 (19pp); [CrossRef]
  9. C. Howson and P. Urbach, Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach (Open Court, 3rd Edition, 2006) p.273.
  10. Joseph Bertrand, Calcul des probabilités (Gauthier-Villars, 1889). 1889.
  11. Nicholas Shackel, Bertrand's Paradox and the Principle of Indifference, Philosophy of Science 74 (2007) 150–175. [CrossRef]
  12. E. T. Jaynes, The Well-Posed Problem, Foundations of Physics 3 (1973) 477–493. [CrossRef]
  13. R. von Mises, Wahrscheinlichkeit, Statistik und Wahrheit (Julius Springer, Vienna, 1928; 2nd. ed. 1936; 3rd ed. 1951) Probability, Statistics and Truth, Second revised English Edition (Allen and Unwin, London, 1957).
  14. Jeffrey M. Mikkelson, “Dissolving the Water/Wine Paradox”, Brit. J. Phil Sci. 55 (2004) 137-145. [CrossRef]
  15. Bas C. van Fraassen, Laws and Symmetry (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989).
  16. E.T. Jaynes, Probability Theory: The Logic of Science (Cambridge University Press, 2003).
  17. M.C.Parker, C.Jeynes, Maximum Entropy (Most Likely) Double Helical and Double Logarithmic Spiral Trajectories in Space-Time, Scientific Reports 9 (2019) 10779 (10 pp, 44 pp Appendices). [CrossRef]
  18. S.W. Corzine, R.H. Yan, L.A. Coldren, A tanh substitution technique for the analysis of abrupt and graded interface multilayer dielectric stacks, IEEE Journal of Quantum Electronics 27 (1991) 2086-2090. [CrossRef]
  19. Torsten A. Enßlin, Jens Jasche, John Skilling, The Physics of Information, Annalen der Physik 531 (2019) 1900059 (2pp). [CrossRef]
  20. Torsten Enßlin, Margret Westerkamp, The Rationality of Irrationality in the Monty Hall Problem, Annalen der Physik 531 (2019) 1800128 (4pp). [CrossRef]
  21. E. T. Jaynes, Where Do We Stand on Maximum Entropy? (1978: in R.D.Rosenkrantz, ed., Papers on Probability, Statistics and Statistical Physics. Synthese Library, vol 158. Springer, Dordrecht, 1989). [CrossRef]
  22. E.T. Jaynes, On the Rationale of Maximum Entropy Methods, Proceedings of the IEEE, 70 (1982) 939-952. [CrossRef]
  23. Marc Burock (2005), “Indifference, sample space, and the Wine/Water Paradox”. Available online: https://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/2487/1/Indifference_new_...Burock_2005.pdf (accessed on 29 March 2023).
  24. M.A.B. Deakin, The Water/Wine Paradox: background, provenance and proposed solutions, Australian Math. Soc. Gazette 33 (2006) 200-205. Available online: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/252476141 (accessed on 29 March 2023).
  25. John D. Norton, Ignorance and Indifference, Phil. of Science 75 (2008) 45-68. Available online: https://doi.org/10.1086/587822. [CrossRef]
  26. Chris Jeynes, Michael C.Parker, Margaret Barker, The Poetics of Physics, Philosophies 8 (2023) 3 (54pp); [CrossRef]
  27. Ariel Caticha, Lectures on Probability, Entropy, and Statistical Physics, Invited lectures at MaxEnt 2008, the 28th International Workshop on Bayesian Inference and Maximum Entropy Methods in Science and Engineering (July 8-13, 2008, Boraceia Beach, Sao Paulo, Brazil). [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.
Copyright: This open access article is published under a Creative Commons CC BY 4.0 license, which permit the free download, distribution, and reuse, provided that the author and preprint are cited in any reuse.
Prerpints.org logo

Preprints.org is a free preprint server supported by MDPI in Basel, Switzerland.

Subscribe

© 2024 MDPI (Basel, Switzerland) unless otherwise stated