“In the microworld, we need uniformity of the strongest kind: complete indistinguishability”. Frank Wilczek and Betsy Devine (1987)
1. Introduction
This is a paper dealing with the logical foundations of quantum theory. There are several aspects to be considered in such an investigation, one of them being the attempt to
represent absolutely indistinguishable objects, as typical in quantum theory, that is, using Wilczek and Devine’s words in the motto,
complete indistinguishability. By this term we understand that if two things are ‘absolutely’, or ‘completely’ indistinguishable, there is no way to discern them, not even in principle or, as Dalla Chiara has put it, not even
in mente Dei (Dalla Chiara, 1985). In mathematical terms, we should not be able to discern things neither by a property nor by a relation. We shall see soon that if we use a standard mathematical framework such as a standard set theory such as ZF, then the distinction
is always possible. Really, the problem with the use of a standard framework, such as a standard set theory, is that we can consider indiscernible elements only within a deformable (not rigid) structure, one admitting nontrivial automorphisms.
1 But this is a bogus solution, for it can be shown that
every structure built in a theory such as the ZF system can be extended to a rigid structure, where the apparently indistinguishable elements are shown to be discernible. Furthermore, the whole universe of sets of a theory such as ZF is rigid (Jech, 2003, p.66), that is, standard set theories are theories of individuals.
2
A typical example of entities of this kind would be quantum objects, which in determined situations cannot be put apart by any device provided by the theory. A sample involves Bose-Einstein Condensates, which can be formed by milliards of ‘completely’ indistinguishable atoms or particles behaving as they were one, forming a big molecule (Ketterle, 2007); despite being many, there is no way to discern them. In some situations, things are a little bit different but the results are similar. Fermions, as is well known, cannot share the same quantum state. If we have more than one, they differ, generally with respect to their spins taken in a certain direction. But, despite the existence of such a ‘difference’, we cannot say which is which, that is, if one of them (suppose being two) has spin UP in a certain direction, which forces the other to have spin DOWN in the same direction, there is no way to say which has spin UP. In this sense, they are also indiscernible in a strong sense (other examples will be mentioned below).
Emphasizing the main problem in using standard mathematics (grounded on classical logic) for describing these entities is that anything
a can always (even if only in principle) be discerned from any other entity
b. The proof is simple; take the unitary set
and define the
identity ofa as
. Done! Only
a has this ‘property’, so there will be a difference to any other
b, that is, to any other entity not obeying
. This is typical of standard mathematics, and it is expected to be so since the theory was designed for coping with individuals.
3 Of course, we can mimic indiscernibles in such frameworks by confining them to deformable (not-rigid) structures, that is, structures having nontrivial automorphisms. But this is a trick since one can prove that in set theories such as the ZFC system, every structure can be extended to a rigid structure (da Costa and Rodrigues, 2007), one that encompasses only the trivial automorphism and, in this extended structure, we realize that the supposed indiscernible entities are, in fact, individuals.
But quantum physics brings questionings to such a view, and according to some, such as Yuri Manin, we “should consider the possibilities of developing a totally new language to speak about infinity"; of course, he is speaking of set theory, and his motivations are collections of quantum objects. Quasi-set theory was elaborated to be such a new theory of the infinite, answering Manin’s problem (Manin, 1976).
4
The main objective of this paper is to show that in the quasi-set theory Q we can construct structures which cannot be extended to rigid structures; in reality, the whole universe of qsets is not rigid, contrary to the standard universe of sets of the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (Jech, 2003, p.66). In order to do so following the standards, we need to speak about automorphisms. Thus I was pushed by Eliza Wajch, whom I thank, in defining automorphism in Q in order to do the next step. I hope this is achieved here.
2. The Core Notions
We shall be working in the quasi-set theory
Q, so we suppose a previous knowledge of it, but we shall provide a minimum in between the text; for references, see (French and Krause, 2006). The theory comprises two kinds of
atoms, entities that are not qsets but which can be elements of qsets, the M-atoms, which mimic the behaviour of the atoms in ZFA (the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with atoms (Suppes, 1972)), and the m-atoms, which are posed to represent quantum entities. To these ones, the standard notion of identity (given by classical logic) does not apply (the original idea that identity is senseless for quantum entities was advanced by Schrödinger (1998), but see French and Krause (2006); we approach this by saying that expressions like ‘
’ (so as their negations) are not well-formed if either
x or
y represents an m-atom. An
extensional identity is defined for M-atoms and qsets (these are the entities that are not atoms).
5
Let
(
) be a q-structure (a structure in
Q) where (to consider the most significative case)
D is a quasi-set (qset) of indiscernible m-atoms and the
are q-relations on
D. We shall consider only binary q-relations to illustrate. We recall that indiscernible m-atoms can are linked by the indistinguishability relation ≡, which has the properties of an equivalence relation but doesn’t obey full substitutivity, as remarked below. Even so, a qset with indistinguishable m-atoms can have a cardinal, a quasi-cardinal, which stands for the quantity of elements it has.
6
A quasi-relation, or q-relation between quasi-sets A and B is a qset of ‘ordered pairs’ , with and , as usual. The notion of ‘ordered pair’ needs to be relativised to indiscernibility – see below; the pair is the qset of the indiscernible from a and from b. A q-relation is a q-function if being and , if , then ; furthermore, no element of A is out of some pair. We can define also q-injections and q-surjections, so also q-bijections, which cope with our intuitions regarding standard functions (for details, please see French and Krause (2006)).
Let be a q-bijective q-function such that, for any and for any relation , . Such a q-function is a candidate to be a q-automorphism of the structure. The most interesting case seems to be that where for every . Since the identity relation doesn’t hold for m-atoms, then, of course, h is not the identity function, which cannot be defined on such a qset.
Suppose that holds for . We shall see that holds as well. In fact, suppose it fails, that is, is the case (let us name this expression ‘★’). Remembering that means (we are supposing that the elements of these qsets belong to D), and that if and , it results that entails as well. Consequently, due to the definition of h, ‘★’ cannot be the case.
This argumentation requires explanation since
Q is a theory that defies our intuitions. Firstly, notice that m-atoms don’t have proper names,
7 that is, the language cannot be extended to a language with a term referring to a
specific m-atom. When we say ‘Peter’ do some m-atom, it stands for
whatever indiscernible from Peter, that is, it makes reference to
something of the kind ‘Peter’, and not a specific object: in a certain sense, all Peters are indiscernible and when some of them is making something, it could be any ‘other’ of them who were doing that, and the results would be the same (invariance by permutations). Thus, proper names, or individual constants in a formal language, here act as individual variables, designating, or having associated to it, a range of possible values, so denoting
kinds of objects. Thus, if
, this means that
some object
of the kindx belongs to some qset of the kind
y. We notice, and insist on noticing that this way of seeing is different to what a classical logician could expect. So, we beg the reader not to judge us from the point of view of classical logic and standard semantics.
The (apparently) only situation where the substitution by indiscernibles doesn’t hold is with respect to the membership relation. Really, let R be membership. Then if and , nothing in the theory grants that . For instance, let y be a strong singleton of x, namely, the qset whose only element (recall that the quasi-cardinality of this qset is one) belongs to D. It should be emphasised that despite such a strong singleton having just one element, we cannot identify it since for doing that we need identity. Thus, even if , the theory doesn’t grant that any indistinguishable from x will belong to any strong singleton of x; these strong singletons are indiscernible, not identical, that is, , but not . Consequently, the equivalence relation ‘≡’ is distinct from identity.
One could argue against this conclusion by suggesting, say, that we can define an identity for m-atoms, for instance as follows: let
x and
y be indiscernible m-atoms and let
and
strong singletons of these elements. Then we can pose
Recall from the short review above that the extensional equality (‘’) applies also to qsets (see the footnote 5) when they have ‘the same elements’. So, since the q-cardinals of both and are one, we may lead of concluding that their elements are the same and hence the defined identity would have the properties of standard identity. But this is a mistake. In the object language, that is, in the language of Q, we cannot say that the elements of these strong singletons are ‘the same’ since this requires identity and then we would be committing a clear petitio principii in assuming that we wish to define. We need to proceed formally: if , we can say that they are (say) *-identical, but never that they are ‘the same’. Furthermore, has not all the properties of standard identity; in particular, it fails substitution. Let us explain.
The Weak Extensionality Axiom (WEA) of Q says that qsets with ‘the same quantity’ (expressed by means of q-cardinals) of ‘elements of the same kind’ (indiscernible among them) are indistinguishable by their way. For instance, the reader may think of two water molecules, so we could write ‘HO ≡ HO’ once they have the same quantity of elements of the same species. The axiom captures things of this kind. But the defined ‘identity’ () is not equivalent to the identity of classical logic, which must obey substitutivity for every formula , that is, we must have (Mendelson, 1997, p.95). Notwithstanding, in Q, let be the formula and let be such that according to the above definition. Then, we should have , but this does not hold.
To see why, we can reason as follows. Suppose with x and denoting indistinguishable m-atoms; insisting, the q-cardinal being 2 suggests that we are in the presence of two indistinguishable m-atoms, two entangled bosons for instance. If and if , even if , there is no sense in saying that belongs to y as well, for in this case, the quasi-cardinal of y would be greater than one, and it is not by the definition of the strong singletons. Furthermore, if both x and belong to y and the q-cardinal of y is one, they should be the same element, and this is not something that the language of Q enables us to do. Really, we should reason as follows: in saying that , with , we are stating that some indistinguishable from x belongs to y, but there is no way the theory grants that such an element is this or that m-atom, since for asserting this we would need identity. But one thing is certain: if an element x belongs to y, then no ‘other’ element can belong to it. The meaning of the word ‘other’ is captured not by identity but by considering the quasi-cardinality of being 2. The same would happen with whatever relation you propose to cope with identity of m-atoms. We make a further remark that if , then the most the theory proves is that , that is, the strong singletons are indiscernible, as resulting from the Weak Extensionality Axiom.
An analogy might be useful here. Suppose a neutral Sodium atom, whose electronic decomposition is 1s 2s 2p 3s. Take the outer shell as a strong singleton of an electron we shall call ‘x’. Of course, the q-cardinal of such a qset is one, but the problem is that although it has just one electron as its element, we cannot state which is it in the sense that we can say that Barak Obama was a US president (that is, a ‘specific’ person; electrons have not such specificities). So, if we consider two electrons of this atom and call them x and , then, as above, the q-cardinal of is two and although they have different quantum numbers (since x is the only electron of the outer shell), we cannot say more than ‘there is one electron in the outer shell and we named it ‘x’ ’. But this does not grant any identification but of course does not belong to the outer shell, which is occupied by just one electron. The individual variables, when referring to m-atoms, act as indefinite descriptions.
A further remark in order here to clarify a little bit more. In saying that , since the quasi-cardinal of the strong singleton is one, we are saying (in Q) that some indiscernible from x is in the strong singleton, but not that the object denoted by x is there, since we cannot attribute to x a specific denotation.
So, the above considerations concerning the q-automorphisms of course presuppose that no relation in is membership, but this is expected in building mathematical structures since membership is already embedded in the underlying logic.