1. Introduction and Why Such Title of the Article
This article is a continuation of [
14,
15,
16]. The main mathematical results of this article were presented at the 25th Conference Applications of Logic in Philosophy and the Foundations of Mathematics, see
http://applications-of-logic.uni.wroc.pl/XXV-Konferencja-Zastosowania-Logiki-w-Filozofii-i-Podstawach-Matematyki. We assume that the current mathematical knowledge
is a finite set of statements which is time-dependent. This set exists only theoretically. Ignoring
and its subsets, sets exist formally in
theory although their properties can be time-dependent (when they depend on
) or informal. In every branch of mathematics, the set of all knowable truths is the set of all theorems. This set exists independently of
. Algorithms always terminate. We explain the distinction between algorithms whose existence is provable in
and constructively defined algorithms which are currently known. By using this distinction, we obtain non-trivial statements on decidable sets
that belong to constructive and informal mathematics and refer to the current mathematical knowledge on
. This and the next sentence justify the article title. For any empirical science, we can identify the current knowledge with that science because truths from the empirical sciences are not necessary truths but working models of truth from a particular context, see [
17, p. 610].
2. Summary of the Main Mathematical Results
For a set whose infiniteness is false or unproven, we define which elements of are classified as known. No known set satisfies Conditions (1)-(4) and is widely known in number theory or naturally defined, where this term has only informal meaning.
(1) A known algorithm with no input returns an integer n satisfying .
(2) A known algorithm for every decides whether or not .
(3) No known algorithm with no input returns the logical value of the statement .
(4) There are many elements of and it is conjectured, though so far unproven, that is infinite.
(5) is naturally defined. The infiniteness of is false or unproven. has the simplest definition among known sets with the same set of known elements.
We prove that the set
satisfies Conditions
(1)-(5) except the requirement that
is naturally defined. We present a table that shows satisfiable conjunctions of the form
where # denotes the negation ¬ or the absence of any symbol.
3. Basic Definitions and Examples
Algorithms always terminate. Semi-algorithms may not terminate. There is the distinction between
existing algorithms (i.e. algorithms whose existence is provable in
) and
known algorithms (i.e. algorithms whose definition is constructive and currently known), see [
2], [
9], [
11, p. 9]. A definition of an integer
n is called
constructive, if it provides a known algorithm with no input that returns
n. Definition 1 applies to sets
whose infiniteness is false or unproven.
Definition 1. We say that a non-negative integer k is a known element of , if and we know an algebraic expression that defines k and consists of the following signs: 1 (one), + (addition), − (subtraction), · (multiplication), ^ (exponentiation with exponent in ), ! (factorial of a non-negative integer), ( (left parenthesis), ) (right parenthesis).
The set of known elements of is finite and time-dependent, so cannot be defined in the formal language of classical mathematics. Let t denote the largest twin prime that is smaller than ((((((((9!)!)!)!)!)!)!)!)!. The number t is an unknown element of the set of twin primes.
Definition 2.
Conditions(1)-(5)concern sets .
(1) A known algorithm with no input returns an integer n satisfying .
(2) A known algorithm for every decides whether or not .
(3) No known algorithm with no input returns the logical value of the statement . (4)There are many elements of and it is conjectured, though so far unproven, that is infinite.
(5) is naturally defined. The infiniteness of is false or unproven. has the simplest definition among known sets with the same set of known elements.
Condition (3) implies that no known proof shows the finiteness/infiniteness of . No known set satisfies Conditions (1)-(4) and is widely known in number theory or naturally defined, where this term has only informal meaning.
Example 1.
The set satisfies Condition (3)
.
Let denote the integer part function.
Example 2.
The set does not satisfy Condition (3)because we know an algorithm with no input that computes . The set of known elements of is empty. Hence, Condition(5)fails for .
Example 3.
([2], [9], [11, p. 9]). The function
is computable because or there exists such that
No known algorithm computes the function h.
Example 4.
The set
is decidable. This satisfies Conditions(1)and(3)and does not satisfy Conditions(2),(4), and(5). These facts will hold forever.
4. Number-Theoretic Results
Edmund Landau’s conjecture states that the set
of primes of the form
is infinite, see [
12,
13,
19].
Statement 1.
Condition (1) remains unproven for .
Proof. For every set
, there exists an algorithm
with no input that returns
This
n satisfies the implication in Condition
(1), but the algorithm
is unknown because its definition is ineffective. □
Statement 2.
The statement
remains unproven in and classical logic without the law of excluded middle.
Let , and let for every positive integer n.
Statement 3.
The set
satisfies Conditions (1)-(4).
Condition (5) fails for .
Proof. Condition
(4) holds as
and the set
is conjecturally infinite. Due to known physics we are not able to confirm by a direct computation that some element of
is greater than
, see [
7]. Thus Condition
(3) holds. Condition
(2) holds trivially. Since the set
is empty or infinite, Condition
(1) holds with
. Condition
(5) fails as the set of known elements of
equals
. □
Statements 4 and 7 provide stronger examples.
Conjecture 1.
([1, p. 443], [4]). The are infinitely many primes of the form .
For a non-negative integer n, let denote .
Statement 4.
The set
satisfies Conditions (1)-(5) e
xcept the requirement that is naturally defined. .
Condition (1) holds with .
.
30
.
Proof. For every integer
, 30 is the smallest integer greater than
. By this, if
, then
. Hence, Condition
(1) holds with
. We explicitly know 24 positive integers
k such that
is prime, see [
3]. The inequality
remains unproven. Since
, Condition
(3) holds. The interval
contains exactly three primes of the form
:
,
,
. For every integer
, the inequality
holds. Therefore, the execution of the following
MuPAD code
m:=0:
for n from 0.0 to 503000.0 do
if n<1!+1 then r:=0 end_if:
if n>=1!+1 and n<2!+1 then r:=1 end_if:
if n>=2!+1 and n<3!+1 then r:=2 end_if:
if n>=3!+1 then r:=3 end_if:
if r>29.5+(11!/(3*n+1))*sin(n) then
m:=m+1:
print([n,m]):
end_if:
end_for:
displays the all known elements of . The output ends with the line , which proves Condition (1) with and Condition (4) with . □
Statement 4 and its proof imply the following corollary.
Corollary 1.
then the following statements holds:
does not satisfy Condition (1),
,
according to the current knowledge, the above upper bound cannot be decreased,
satisfies Conditions (2)-(4),
the infiniteness of is false or unproven.
Definition 3.
Conditions (1a)-(5a)concern sets .
(1a) A known algorithm with no input returns a positive integer n satisfying .
(2a) A known algorithm for every decides whether or not .
(3a) No known algorithm with no input returns the logical value of the statement .
(4a)There are many elements of and it is conjectured, though so far unproven, that is finite.
(5a) is naturally defined. The finiteness of is false or unproven. has the simplest definition among known sets with the same set of known elements.
Statement 5.
The set
satisfies Conditions (1a)-(5a) except the requirement that is naturally defined. .
Condition (1a) holds with .
.
7
.
Proof. For every integer
, 7 is the smallest integer greater than
. By this, if
, then
. Hence, Condition
(1a) holds with
. It is conjectured that
is a square only for
, see [
18, p. 297]. Hence, the inequality
remains unproven. Since
, Condition
(3a) holds. The interval
contains exactly three squares of the form
:
,
,
. Therefore, the execution of the following
MuPAD code
m:=0:
for n from 0.0 to 1000000.0 do
if n<25 then r:=0 end_if:
if n>=25 and n<121 then r:=1 end_if:
if n>=121 and n<5041 then r:=2 end_if:
if n>=5041 then r:=3 end_if:
if r>6.5+(1000000/(3*n+1))*sin(n) then
m:=m+1:
print([n,m]):
end_if:
end_for:
displays the all known elements of . The output ends with the line , which proves Condition (1a) with and Condition (4a) with . □
Statement 6.
The set
satisfies the conjunction
To formulate Statement 7 and its proof, we need some lemmas. For a non-negative integer n, let denote the largest integer divisor of smaller than n. For a non-negative integer n, let denote the largest integer divisor of smaller than n.
Lemma 1. For every integer , . For every integer , .
Lemma 2. For every integer , .
Proof. 6553600 equals
and divides
.
.
. We need to prove that every integer
does not divide
. It holds as the set
contains 6553600 and 7812500 as consecutive elements. □
Lemma 3. The number is prime.
Proof. The following
PARI/GP ([
8]) command
isprime(6553600^2+1,{flag=2})
returns 1. This command performs the
APRCL primality test, the best deterministic primality test algorithm ([
20, p. 226]). It rigorously shows that the number
is prime. □
In the next lemmas, the execution of the command
isprime(n,{
flag=2}
) proves the primality of
n. Let
denote the function
Lemma 4. The set is infinite.
Proof. Let
. By the inequality
and Lemma 1, for every non-negative integer
m, the number
is prime. □
Before Open Problem 1, denotes the set .
Lemma 5. For every and for every non-negative integer j, .
Proof. By the inequality
and Lemma 1,
□
Lemma 6. .
Proof. By Lemmas 2 and 3, for every even integer
, the number
is prime. Hence,
Consequently,
□
Lemma 7. and .
Proof. The number
divides
. Hence,
. The number
is prime. The set
contains 10000 and 12500 as consecutive elements. Hence,
. The number
is composite. □
Statement 7.
The set satisfies Conditions (1)-(5) except the requirement that is naturally defined.
Proof. Condition (2) holds trivially. Let denote . By Lemma 5, Condition (1) holds for . Lemma 5 and the unproven statement show Condition (3). The same argument and Lemma 6 yield Condition (4). By Lemma 4, the set is infinite. Since Definition 1 applies to sets whose infiniteness is false or unproven, Condition (5) holds except the requirement that is naturally defined. □
The set satisfies Condition (5) except the requirement that is naturally defined. It is true because is infinite by Lemma 4 and Definition 1 applies only to sets whose infiniteness is false or unproven. Ignoring this restriction, still satisfies the same identical condition due to Lemma 7.
Proposition 1.
No set will satisfy Conditions(1)-(4)forever, if for every algorithm with no input, at some future day, a computer will be able to execute this algorithm in 1 second or less.
Proof. The proof goes by contradiction. We fix an integer
n that satisfies Condition
(1). Since Conditions
(1)-(3) will hold forever, the semi-algorithm in
Figure 1 never terminates and sequentially prints the following sentences:
Figure 1.
Semi-algorithm that terminates if and only if is infinite.
Figure 1.
Semi-algorithm that terminates if and only if is infinite.
The sentences from the sequence
(T) and our assumption imply that for every integer
computed by a known algorithm, at some future day, a computer will be able to confirm in 1 second or less that
. Thus, at some future day, numerical evidence will support the conjecture that the set
is finite, contrary to the conjecture in Condition
(4). □
The physical limits of computation ([
7]) disprove the assumption of Proposition 1.
Openproblem 1.
Is there a set which satisfies Conditions (1)-(5)?
Open Problem 1 asks about the existence of a year
in which the conjunction
will hold for some
. For every year
and for every
, a positive solution to Open Problem
i in the year
t may change in the future. Currently, the answers to Open Problems 1–5 are negative.
5. Satisfiable Conjunctions Which Consist of Conditions (1)-(5) and Their Negations
The set
satisfies the conjunction
The set
satisfies the conjunction
The numbers
are prime for
. It is open whether or not there are infinitely many primes of the form
, see [
6, p. 158] and [
10, p. 74]. It is open whether or not there are infinitely many composite numbers of the form
, see [
6, p. 159] and [
10, p. 74]. Most mathematicians believe that
is composite for every integer
, see [
5, p. 23]. The set
satisfies the conjunction
Openproblem 2.
Is there a set that satisfies the conjunction
The set
satisfies the conjunction
Openproblem 3.
Is there a set that satisfies the conjunction
It is possible, although very doubtful, that at some future day, the set will solve Open Problem 2. The same is true for Open Problem 3. It is possible, although very doubtful, that at some future day, the set will solve Open Problem 1. The same is true for Open Problems 2 and 3.
Table 1 shows satisfiable conjunctions of the form
where # denotes the negation ¬ or the absence of any symbol.
Table 1.
Five satisfiable conjunctions.
Table 1.
Five satisfiable conjunctions.
Definition 4. We say that an integer n is a threshold number of a set , if .
If a set is empty or infinite, then any integer n is a threshold number of . If a set is non-empty and finite, then the all threshold numbers of form the set .
Openproblem 5.
Is there a known threshold number of ?
Open Problem 5 asks about the existence of a year in which the implication will hold for some known integer n.
Let denote the set of twin primes. Is there a known threshold number of ?
Open Problem 4 asks about the existence of a year in which the implication will hold for some known integer n.
References
- C. K. Caldwell and Y. Gallot, On the primality of n! ±1 and 2 × 3 × 5 × ⋯×p±1, Math. Comp. 71 (2002), no. [CrossRef]
- J. Case and M. Ralston, Beyond Rogers’ non-constructively computable function, in: The nature of computation, Lecture Notes in Comput. Sci., 7921, 45–54, Springer, Heidelberg, 2013, http://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-642-39053-1_6.
-
Factorial prime, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Factorial_prime.
-
Is n! + 1 often a prime?, http://math.stackexchange.com/questions/853085/is-n-1-often-a-prime.
- J.-M. De Koninck and F. Luca, Analytic number theory: Exploring the anatomy of integers, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2012.
- M. Křížek, F. Luca, L. Somer, 17 lectures on Fermat numbers: from number theory to geometry, Springer, New York, 2001.
- S. Lloyd, Ultimate physical limits to computation, Nature 406 (2000), 1047–1054, http://doi.org/10.1038/35023282. [CrossRef]
-
PARI/GPonline documentation, http://pari.math.u-bordeaux.fr/dochtml/html/Arithmetic_functions.html.
- R. Reitzig, How can it be decidable whether πhas some sequence o f digits?, http://cs.stackexchange.com/questions/367/how-can-it-be-decidable-whether-pi-has-some-sequence-of-digits.
- P. Ribenboim, The little book of bigger primes, 2nd ed., Springer, New York, 2004.
- H. Rogers, Jr., Theory of recursive functions and effective computability, 2nd ed., MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1987.
- N. J. A. Sloane, The On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences, A002496, Primes of the form n2 + 1, http://oeis.org/A002496.
- N. J. A. Sloane, The On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences, A083844, Number of primes of the form x2 + 1 < 10 n, http://oeis.org/A083844.
- A. Tyszka, Statements and open problems on decidable sets X ⊆ N that refer to the current knowledge on X, Journal of Applied Computer Science & Mathematics 16 (2022), no. 2, 31–35, http://www.jacsm.ro/view/?pid=34_5, http://doi.org/10.4316/JACSM.202202005. [CrossRef]
- A. Tyszka, Statements and open problems on decidable sets X ⊆ N, Pi Mu Epsilon J. 15 (2023), no. 8, 493–504.
- A. Tyszka, Statements and open problems on decidable sets X ⊆ N that contain informal notions and refer to the current knowledge on X, Creat. Math. Inform. 32 (2023), no. 2, 247–253, http://semnul.com/creative-mathematics/wp-content/uploads/2023/07/creative_2023_32_2_247_253.pdf, http://doi.org/10.37193/CMI.2023.02.12. [CrossRef]
- B. L. J. Webb, Science, Truth, and Meaning: From Wonder to Understanding, World Scientific, Singapore, 2021.
- E. W. Weisstein, CRC Concise Encyclopedia of Mathematics, 2nd ed., Chapman & Hall/CRC, Boca Raton, FL, 2002.
- Wolfram MathWorld, Landau’s Problems, http://mathworld.wolfram.com/LandausProblems.html.
- S. Y. Yan, Number theory for computing, 2nd ed., Springer, Berlin, 2002.
|
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).