1. Introduction and why such title of the article
We assume that the current mathematical knowledge
is a finite set of statements from both formal and constructive mathematics, which is time-dependent and publicly available. Any theorem of any mathematician of any time belongs to
. This set exists only theoretically. Ignoring
and its subsets, sets exist formally in
theory although their properties can be time-dependent (when they depend on
) or informal. In every branch of mathematics, the set of all knowable truths is the set of all theorems. This set exists independently of
. Algorithms always terminate. We explain the distinction between algorithms whose existence is provable in
and constructively defined algorithms which are currently known. By using this distinction, we obtain non-trivial statements on decidable sets
that belong to constructive and informal mathematics and refer to the current mathematical knowledge on
. This and the next sentence justify the article title. For any empirical science, we can identify the current knowledge with that science because truths from the empirical sciences are not necessary truths but working models of truth from a particular context, see [
16], p. 610. The presented mathematical results are a continuation or a repetition of the main results of [
15].
2. Basic definitions and examples
Algorithms always terminate. Semi-algorithms may not terminate. There is the distinction between
existing algorithms (i.e. algorithms whose existence is provable in
) and
known algorithms (i.e. algorithms whose definition is constructive and currently known), see [
2,
9] and [
11] p. 9. A definition of an integer
n is called
constructive, if it provides a known algorithm with no input that returns
n. Definition 1 applies to sets
whose infiniteness is false or unproven.
Definition 1. We say that a non-negative integer k is a known element of , if and we know an algebraic expression that defines k and consists of the following signs: 1 (one), + (addition), − (subtraction), · (multiplication), ^ (exponentiation with exponent in ), ! (factorial of a non-negative integer), ( (left parenthesis), ) (right parenthesis).
The set of known elements of is finite and time-dependent, so cannot be defined in the formal language of classical mathematics. Let t denote the largest twin prime that is smaller than ((((((((9!)!)!)!)!)!)!)!)!. The number t is an unknown element of the set of twin primes.
Definition 2.
Conditions (1)-(5) concern sets .
(1) A known algorithm with no input returns an integer n satisfying .
(2) A known algorithm for every decides whether or not .
(3)No known algorithm with no input returns the logical value of the statement .
(4) There are many elements of and it is conjectured, though so far unproven, that is infinite.
(5) is naturally defined. The infiniteness of is false or unproven. has the simplest definition among known sets with the same set of known elements.
Condition (3) implies that no known proof shows the finiteness/infiniteness of . No known set satisfies Conditions (1)-(4) and is widely known in number theory or naturally defined, where this term has only informal meaning.
Let denote the integer part function.
Example 1.
The set does not satisfy Condition (3) because we know an algorithm with no input that computes . The set of known elements of is empty. Hence, Condition (5) fails for .
Example 2.
([2,9] and [11] p. 9). The function
is computable because or there exists such that
No known algorithm computes the function h.
Example 3.
The set
is decidable. This satisfies Conditions (1) and (3) and does not satisfy Conditions (2) , (4) , and (5) . These facts will hold forever.
3. Number-theoretic results
Edmund Landau’s conjecture states that the set
of primes of the form
is infinite, see [
13,
14,
18].
Statement 1.
Condition (1) remains unproven for .
Proof. For every set
, there exists an algorithm
with no input that returns
This n satisfies the implication in Condition (1), but the algorithm is unknown because its definition is ineffective. □
Statement 2.
remains unproven in and classical logic without the law of excluded middle.
Conjecture 1. ([1] p. 443, [4]). The are infinitely many primes of the form .
For a non-negative integer n, let denote .
Statement 3.
satisfies Conditions (1)-(5) except the requirement that is naturally defined. . Condition (1) holds with . . 30 .
Proof. For every integer
, 30 is the smallest integer greater than
. By this, if
, then
. Hence, Condition
(1) holds with
. We explicitly know 24 positive integers
k such that
is prime, see [
3]. The inequality
remains unproven. Since
, Condition
(3) holds. The interval
contains exactly three primes of the form
:
,
,
. For every integer
, the inequality
holds. Therefore, the execution of the following
MuPAD code
m:=0:
for n from 0.0 to 503000.0 do
if n<1!+1 then r:=0 end_if:
if n>=1!+1 and n<2!+1 then r:=1 end_if:
if n>=2!+1 and n<3!+1 then r:=2 end_if:
if n>=3!+1 then r:=3 end_if:
if r>29.5+(11!/(3*n+1))*sin(n) then
m:=m+1:
print([n,m]):
end_if:
end_for:
displays the all known elements of . The output ends with the line , which proves Condition (1) with and Condition (4) with . □
T. Nagell proved in [
8] (cf. [
12], p. 104) that the equation
has exactly 16 integer solutions, namely
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
. The set
has exactly 23 elements. Among them, there are 14 integers from the interval
. Let
denote the set
From [
14], it is known that
. Hence,
and 14 elements of
can be practically computed. The inequality
remains unproven. The last two sentences and Statement 3 imply the following corollary.
Corollary 1. If we add to , then the following statements hold:
does not satisfy Condition (1) ,
,
the above lower bound is currently the best known,
,
the above upper bound is currently the best known,
satisfies Conditions (2)-(5) except the requirement that is naturally defined.
Analogical statements hold, if we add to the set
Definition 3.
Conditions (1a)-(5a) concern sets .
(1a) A known algorithm with no input returns a positive integer n satisfying .
(2a) A known algorithm for every decides whether or not .
(3a)No known algorithm with no input returns the logical value of the statement .
(4a) There are many elements of and it is conjectured, though so far unproven, that is finite.
(5a) is naturally defined. The finiteness of is false or unproven. has the simplest definition among known sets with the same set of known elements.
Statement 4.
satisfies Conditions (1a)-(5a) except the requirement that is naturally defined. . Condition (1a) holds with . . 7 .
Proof. For every integer
, 7 is the smallest integer greater than
. By this, if
, then
. Hence, Condition
(1a) holds with
. It is conjectured that
is a square only for
, see [
17, p. 297]. Hence, the inequality
remains unproven. Since
, Condition
(3a) holds. The interval
contains exactly three squares of the form
:
,
,
. Therefore, the execution of the following
MuPAD code
m:=0:
for n from 0.0 to 1000000.0 do
if n<25 then r:=0 end_if:
if n>=25 and n<121 then r:=1 end_if:
if n>=121 and n<5041 then r:=2 end_if:
if n>=5041 then r:=3 end_if:
if r>6.5+(1000000/(3*n+1))*sin(n) then
m:=m+1:
print([n,m]):
end_if:
end_for:
displays the all known elements of . The output ends with the line , which proves Condition (1a) with and Condition (4a) with . □
Statement 5.
satisfies the conjunction
For a non-negative integer n, let denote the largest integer divisor of smaller than n. Let be defined by setting to be the exponent of 2 in the prime factorization of .
Statement 6.
satisfies Conditions (1)-(5) except the requirement that is naturally defined. Condition (1) holds with .
Statement 7.
No set will satisfy Conditions (1)-(4) forever, if for every algorithm with no input, at some future day, a computer will be able to execute this algorithm in 1 second or less.
Proof. The proof goes by contradiction. We fix an integer
n that satisfies Condition
(1). Since Conditions
(1)-(3) will hold forever, the semi-algorithm in
Figure 1 never terminates and sequentially prints the following sentences:
The sentences from the sequence (T) and our assumption imply that for every integer computed by a known algorithm, at some future day, a computer will be able to confirm in 1 second or less that . Thus, at some future day, numerical evidence will support the conjecture that the set is finite, contrary to the conjecture in Condition (4). □
The physical limits of computation ([
7]) disprove the assumption of Statement 7.
Open Problem 1.
Is there a set which satisfies Conditions(1)-(5)?
Open Problem 1 asks about the existence of a year
in which the conjunction
will hold for some
. For every year
and for every
, a positive solution to Open Problem
i in the year
t may change in the future. Currently, the answers to Open Problems 1–5 are negative.
4. Satisfiable conjunctions which consist of Conditions (1)-(5) and their negations
The set
satisfies the conjunction
The set
satisfies the conjunction
The numbers
are prime for
. It is open whether or not there are infinitely many primes of the form
, see [
6] p. 158 and [
10] p. 74. It is open whether or not there are infinitely many composite numbers of the form
, see [
6] p. 159 and [
10] p. 74. Most mathematicians believe that
is composite for every integer
, see [
5] p. 23. Let
, and let
for every positive integer
n. The set
satisfies the conjunction
Open Problem 2.
Is there a set that satisfies the conjunction
The set
satisfies the conjunction
Open Problem 3.
Is there a set that satisfies the conjunction
It is possible, although very doubtful, that at some future day, the set will solve Open Problem 2. The same is true for Open Problem 3. It is possible, although very doubtful, that at some future day, the set will solve Open Problem 1. The same is true for Open Problems 2 and 3.
Table 1 shows satisfiable conjunctions of the form
where # denotes the negation ¬ or the absence of any symbol.
Definition 4. We say that an integer n is a threshold number of a set , if .
If a set is empty or infinite, then any integer n is a threshold number of . If a set is non-empty and finite, then the all threshold numbers of form the set .
Open Problem 4. Is there a known threshold number of ?
Open Problem 4 asks about the existence of a year in which the implication will hold for some known integer n.
Let denote the set of twin primes.
Open Problem 5. Is there a known threshold number of ?
Open Problem 5 asks about the existence of a year in which the implication will hold for some known integer n.