In the following, we will give an overview of the results of the interviews: firstly of the understanding of alternative methods, secondly, regarding the spectrum of all the reasons identified for the use of animal or alternative models. Additionally, some of the reasons are evaluated ethically. Thereby, we will only take up a part of the reasons identified to illustrate relevant ethical aspects.
What are exemplary ethical dimensions of the reasons?
Personal attitudes: Based on the (current) societal norm setting, which basically allows animal experiments, robust ethical principles and a defined procedure for third party approval (competent authorities) are safeguards for ethically defensible research involving animals.
Knowing these safeguards may be enough for some researchers. They may not need to think any further. In that sense, saying “I choose the animal model because it can be justified and ethically acceptable” (PA2.1, Tab. 2) could imply a reference to a general attitude to “delegate” the decision to a “higher” level of decision-making. For others, emotions play a stronger role, for example, “I choose the alternatives because experiments with animals are stressing me emotionally/psychologically” (PA1.3). Ethical dimensions: None of these personal attitudes is prima facie ethically better or worse. Instead, they are expressions of different implicit assumptions. Following the Value Judgment Model, descriptive premises, such as “the established approval procedure is most likely to lead to a ‘correct’ decision about moral permissibility” (even though others may disagree), or “my active role and the suffering I am directly confronted with affect me too much personally,” can be rationally reconstructed from the interviews. The latter example also implies an evaluative backing that suffering (in general or specifically also regarding animals) is ethically not good – otherwise it would not be experienced as emotionally burdensome.
Furthermore, personal attitudes are grounded in a)
values/principles (“protecting a human being from ineffective or harmful drugs is a higher value than refraining from animal experiments,” PA2.4), b)
emotions (PA1.3 see above) or c)
interests (“I am curious to try new things,”, PA1.1).
Ethical dimensions: Such personal attitudes are legitimate for any person. They cannot, however, serve well as
impersonal normative justifications (claiming to give intersubjective comprehensible reasons for the rightness or wrongness of an action) but only as
personal justifications (claiming only to state why this particular person has judged a particular action to be right or wrong and/or has preferred it or refrained from it) (cf. [
28]). This is because, for example, emotions or desires are not generalizable, nor are personal experiences or personality structures and associated interests. However, some issues should be discussed from an ethical perspective. These considerations are referred to as
secondary interests in the concept of conflicts of interest in the professional context. It is important to note that primary and secondary interests are often not in conflict with each other, but can even have positive effects (personal curiosity of a scientist). However, if they are conflicting with
primary interests (e.g., the pursuit to produce relevant and valid findings or adherence to the six principles of animal research ethics), they should not influence the professional judgement inappropriately [
29]. This could violate a general norm of objectivity or
disinterestedness (as expressed, for example, in the Mertonian norms/ethos of science [
30]). In addition, if someone argues that conducting animal experiments stresses them emotionally, this probably (implicitly) refers to a general/abstract moral norm, such as ‘do not harm others’ or ‘thou shalt not kill.’ These norms are presumably shared by significantly more people than the (fictitious) motivation of “striving for media attention,” which would primarily satisfy a personal need.
In sum, personal attitudes influence decision-making (such as on a disease model) or our positions towards certain professional issues (e.g., conflict of interest issues or scientific integrity). As an interpretation/reconstruction, for example, on the basis of the Value Judgment Model, suggests, it is necessary in each case to examine whether emotions (but perhaps also interests) are based on general and consensual moral norms that appear as implicit evaluative backings. In such cases, however, the norms should be brought into focus because they allow for an impersonal normative justification. Therefore, it is ethically important to look at the further justifications (“argumentative backings”) of such seemingly purely personal attitudes.
Work environment: Some scientists argue that “alternatives are associated with smaller amounts of lengthy bureaucracy (e.g., no approval procedure)” (WE1.2). Ethical dimensions: The evaluative assumption (and, thus, premise in the justification structure) behind this might be that “lengthy bureaucratic processes are bad for / are a hindrance to research.” It should be noted that this is a specific perspective that emphasizes efficiency, which can be understood as a shared value or (ethical) principle in science, and especially in research within the health-care system (given that public resources are being spent). However, in the research context, the scientific validity of the findings or the ethical integrity of the scientific project is probably more important than efficiency, i.e., a higher value must be placed on validity or integrity in a weighing process. This does not mean that efficiency cannot be taken into account, but decisions should not be made only in favor of efficiency (and against, for example, validity) – choosing an alternative method only because it means less bureaucratic effort would be ethically questionable as long as validity and integrity requirements are not sufficiently fulfilled. After all, bureaucracy, however burdensome, is not an end in itself but a best practice to ensure the validity and integrity of research.
Other aspects of the work environment can also play a role in the choice of a disease model. Some researchers, for example, report that “superiors are demanding or are explicitly supporting the use of alternative methods” (WE1-9) or “my supervisor has decided so” (WE2.4). Ethical dimensions: There is a mutual dependence or dependent relationships in academia (as well as in private sector). It is important to be aware of these and their possible influence on our decisions via the definition or modification of descriptive assumptions or, above all, evaluative assumptions (and the values behind them). This is important because conflicts can arise between one’s own evaluative assumptions and those decisions and actions that one must follow or support as a team member. In extreme cases, this can lead to moral distress, a feeling of helplessness that what one feels to be ethically right is not being done, and that one cannot (adequately) influence this due to hierarchies.
A further important context factor that was brought up in the spectrum of reasons is the relevance of available or necessary infrastructure (WE1.4 and WE2.2-3). If animal laboratories and related expertise are already available, and the switch to an alternative method is, therefore, assumed to be too costly, this may influence the decision. Conversely, researchers who only work in vitro, for example, will have neither the infrastructure nor expertise for animal research, and if they do want to resort to animal experiments, they will have to outsource them (e.g., via cooperation partners) (WE1.5, Interview 10). Ethical dimensions: Similar to bureaucratic requirements, actions based on existing or required infrastructure do not necessarily violate an ethical principle. Again, however, it would become ethically problematic if scientific validity or integrity were negatively influenced, or, in extreme cases, if animal experiments were carried out that were, strictly speaking, not absolutely necessary (Principle of No Alternative Method) – simply because the infrastructure would only allow animal experiments to be performed.
Science: Statements belonging to this part of the spectrum of reasons are always specific to a field of research. This means that for statements such as “I find the transferability of animal models to humans inadequate” (S1.5) or “I lack confidence in the potential of alternatives” (A2.5), a “related to my research field XY” should be added in the mind. This contextualization becomes clear in statements such as “complex questions/interactions can only be investigated in the whole organism” (S2.2), which seems to be more obvious in some fields than others. Ethical dimensions: Such an assumption forms, more or less directly, the descriptive premise in the justification of an animal experiment, likely to be combined with an evaluative premise based on the Principle of No Alternative Method. (In the theory of principlism, it is also conceivable that the Principle of No Alternative Method is specified accordingly on the basis of this descriptive information, so that it says, for example: “If no alternative methods are available or suitable for studying complex issues or interactions in the whole organism, then, prima facie, an animal experiment may be carried out.”)
Other researchers argue that (regarding their research field): “I get publishable results faster when I am using an alternative” (S1.12). Ethical dimensions: At first glance, this does not seem so ethically significant. However, if one considers the fact that only published findings can fulfill the central promise of generating value through research, this can be a descriptive premise relevant for respecting the Principle of Sufficient Value to Justify Harm (though it is not sufficient to fulfill it).
In contrast to such examples of reasons that can be attributed more or less directly to justifications using ethical principles, there are pragmatic considerations, especially regarding the usability of the results. Ethical dimensions: A researcher’s interest or need to commercialize their work is initially legitimate (“the industry often demands results from animal models, and otherwise commercialization of our results is hardly possible,” S2.6).
We further extracted the argument that some researchers continue to work in basic and translational research with animal models because “science has 50 to 60 years of experience with certain animal models” (WE2.6). Ethical dimensions: The plausible descriptive premise is that there is a lot of experience and achievement with these animal models that have helped to advance science. Whether these benefits exist and, if yes, what their magnitude is, has to be addressed very field-specifically and should be documented in a comprehensible and systematic manner. If this is based more on financial considerations (e.g., avoiding the need to invest in infrastructure), this is more problematic from an ethical point of view (probably violating the Principle of No Alternative Method and Principle of No Unnecessary Harm). In specific fields and to a certain extent, there may be legitimate reasons why a more suitable model cannot be implemented in a specific situation, i.e., does not represent the “best choice.” However, scientific factors and animal welfare should usually be decisive.
Another issue that should be discussed is that both animal models and alternatives “imitate the human organism only to a limited extent” (S1.1+5 and S2.7). We should be clear what kind and scale of uncertainties we want to accept when going from preclinical to clinical research and, thus, begin to involve humans. Do these uncertainties tend to be larger, equal or smaller for alternative models? Perhaps this premise is wrong because these uncertainties related to the use of alternative methods impress more that the common and known uncertainties in animal models. Finding a clear answer to this question is not made any easier by the replication crisis (e.g., [
31,
32]) and biases in the risk assessment based on investigator brochures [
33,
34].
Ethical dimensions: From an ethical point of view, it concerns the meaningfulness and the (social) benefit, which must be empirically proven and critically reflected on a field-specific basis (
Principle of Expected Net Benefit and
Principle of No Unnecessary Harm). Against the background of dynamic technological developments (e.g., new opportunities through artificial intelligence), this should be done on an ongoing basis.
Researchers have to continually find
sources of funding and, thereby, orient themselves to the external (public) research funders. Great investment into new technology and the qualification of personnel to use it is currently required for a shift more towards alternative methods, and if the investment costs are funded, this is beneficial (WE1.10+13).
Ethical dimensions: This is not part of a sound justification. There is hardly any evaluative descriptive premise that would be sufficiently credible – from an ethical perspective – to justify the conclusion (thus, the value judgement) that ‘The animal experiment is the better choice.’ An evaluative premise, such as ‘It is good/right to conduct an animal experiment (at least better than not conducting any research) if an alternative is generally available but cannot be adequately funded in this case,’ may be the one that formally enables justification. However, it obviously opens up countless exceptions to the
Principle of No Alternative Method, which is a quite uncontroversial and also, as mentioned in the introduction, legally defended. Briefly, it does not make the use of animal experiments “more right”
if alternatives were available or could conceivably be developed but neither are sufficiently paid for. However, with reference to the
ought-implies-can principle (simplified: one can only demand normatively what is also realistically realizable) (e.g., [
35]), it could be argued that animals are
the only possible disease model in this case. Nevertheless, whether the specified ethical principle following the
Principle of No Alternative Method would then not have to be “no animal experiment if an alternative is available but financially unfeasible” must be examined in each individual case (e.g., to what extent is the alternative available but not available, to what extent would it be suitable).
Animal welfare: All reasons that are subsumed under this category in the spectrum of reasons are either easily complemented by principles of animal research ethics (when the reasons are referring to descriptive assumptions) or are, in the end, specifications of these principles (e.g., “thereby allowing various pre-experiments that may otherwise cause animal experiments” (A1.2),
Principle of No Unnecessary Harm and
Principle of Sufficient Value to Justify Harm). Given these principles, current (animal protection) laws, and social and political movements that aim to improve animal welfare (or even rights), it must be a guiding consideration in decisions.
Ethical dimensions: It is especially difficult to argue why animal welfare should be restricted in favor of mere pragmatic contextual factors – all the more so when an ethical stance is taken that always gives priority to the
moral point of view or the
moral position over other points of view, especially self-interest (e.g., [
36,
37]). Therefore, this only seems possible where pragmatic reasons can refer to ethical values and principles in their argumentative backings. However, as shown by way of the example above, this will seldom occur. Even if it does, whether the weighing up between different ethical values or principles is convincing must then also be examined again. By contrast, defined constraints are conceivable in favor of scientific considerations (e.g., validity) and their related ethical values (e.g., social benefit), whereby the appropriateness must always be checked in a review process by third parties.