Preprint
Article

What Is a Disease for Doctors? A Realist Thematic Analysis and Implications for Medical Education

Altmetrics

Downloads

116

Views

42

Comments

0

A peer-reviewed article of this preprint also exists.

Submitted:

29 April 2024

Posted:

29 April 2024

You are already at the latest version

Alerts
Abstract
Given the long-standing debate about the nature of the concept of disease, the objective of this study was to understand how doctors categorize a condition as a disease or not and what kind of information they use. A survey with a set of clinical vignettes was designed, and a group of physicians were asked to interpret those situations as a disease or not and to motivate their choice with a short written text. Thematic analysis of the answers resulted in four themes: the temporal dimension of a disease, reification of disease, disease as an existential condition, and disease as a motivation to action. The respondents’ interpretations were very heterogeneous, supporting the idea that physicians do not share a common prototypical concept of disease. An interpretation of these results according to a critical realist and systemic approach suggested that the doctor-patient relationship is the context able to influence the interpretation of a condition as a disease or not as the final outcome of a process in which both objective, subjective, and socially mediated elements are taken into consideration.
Keywords: 
Subject: Medicine and Pharmacology  -   Clinical Medicine

1. Introduction

The attempt to conceptualize what is a disease has been a long matter of discussion, past and present [1]. To philosophers, the definitions of a disease had been historically divided into three main categories: pure naturalist [2], pure normative [3], and a pragmatic approach, representing a combination of the two. The naturalist definition considers disease as a biological change or dysfunction. In contrast, the normative definition is shaped by social norms, categorizing certain behaviors as undesirable or deviating from accepted moral and behavioral standards, out of the range of what is considered normal. The pragmatic definition considers a collection of biological, functional, and normative components [4,5,6].
Some philosophers indeed questioned the need to define a disease, because “the concept of disease does not in fact play the crucial role in clinical decision making” [7] p.2. Despite his provocative and sceptical way of thought, Hesslow [7] listed four purposes for the definition of a disease: to allow the initiation of a diagnostic inquiry or medical treatment, to ensure welfare, to relieve from the obligation to work, and, in the case of mental illness, to relieve moral responsibility and legal liability.
Others proposed a matter-of-fact approach to the problem,” a more realistic description of the way we build, use, apply, and change our concept of disease.” [8] p.424 and that “‘Disease’ is not a theoretical concept, but a practical term.” [8] p.432. The issue to address adequately such concept becomes more complex once related but not overlapping concepts such as illness, sickness, dysfunction, disorder, and health are brought in consideration [9]. Diving deeper into the subject, there are voices not yet considered when attempting to define a disease: what do doctors, and medical educators think? How do doctors and medical educators use the concept of disease in their professional decision-making and actions?
To the authors’ knowledge, only one study investigated whether doctors had a conceptual prototype of diseases. Hoffman conducted a quantitative study based on a survey of two hundred and twenty-three Norwegian physicians. The physicians were given an extensive list of conditions and were asked to rank them. Ranking was based on considering those conditions as diseases. Because of the wide variability in response, the study falsified the hypothesis that disease was a prototypical concept. Unfortunately, because of its quantitative approach, this study did not explain the variability observed in labelling a condition as a disease or not [10].
From an educational perspective, the only apparent concern is to support students in developing the concept of illness as a dimension of patient suffering, with the same importance as the concept of disease as an organic or functional alteration. [11,12] This could be achieved through developing communication skills and understanding of the patient’s background not only on a pathophysiological level, allowing future physicians to consider the patient’s perception on her or his condition [13,14].
The objective of this study was to gain a more profound understanding of how doctors categorize a condition, interpretating it as a disease or not, and what is the lead of information they use in the process. Another guiding question was what the purpose of such labelling is. The goal was to suggest to medical educators some theory-based pedagogies to create an integration of different definitions and points of view, helping their students to develop a more mature professional identity.
The research questions were:
-
What are the information leads that doctors use to decide whether a condition is a disease?
-
What are the perspectives from which doctors decide whether a condition is a disease or not?
-
What purposes do doctors consider in labelling a condition as a disease?
This article is adherent to the Standard for Reporting Qualitative Research (SRQR) [15].

2. Materials and Methods

We designed a survey based on a set of clinical vignettes and submitted it to a group of doctors and senior medical students, asking them to identify each condition as a disease or not and to motivate their decision.
As briefly discussed above, the definition of disease varies according to different ontologies and epistemologies. Hence, to acknowledge and manage this heterogeneity, we needed a flexible theoretical approach while analysing the data. For this reason, thematic analysis based on the critical realist approach was deemed the most appropriate.

2.1. Theoretical Foundation

Thematic analysis is a technique that organizes and elaborate a set of data in detail. It is a mean of finding, inductively analysing and reporting patterns (themes) within the data [16]. By itself, thematic analysis can support different types of theoretical orientations in the interpretation of data. A critical realist approach was adopted to interpret the findings of this thematic analysis [17,18,19].
Critical realism holds that the universe, including the social world, exists. The basic ontology of critical realism holds that there are entities that can be material (an object), immaterial (a class) or both (an X-ray report, which is both information and a document). Entities have internal causal power and are related to each other in a world conceived as an open system [20]. The result of the interaction of entities and their power is not based on a linear cause-and-effect mechanism, but is rather a pattern of events, a tendency [17]. Critical realism admits that attempts to determine the nature of the world is fallible, but it is possible to gain a critical understanding of entities like the self, society, and its structures, and that one can develop theories specific to each domain. The task of a researcher is to develop a reliable explanation of events, tendencies, or outcomes, avoiding any rigid, context- based framework of cause-and-effect. Critical realism focuses on finding out what might work, how, and for whom, on a specific intervention, in a specific context. A critical realist account generally describes these variables in terms of contexts, mechanisms, and outcomes (CMOs). CMO configurations are used to explain why particular interventions succeeded or failed and how contexts and mechanisms affected the outcomes. Finally, critical realism embraces a view of the world as an open, stratified system with recurring looping effects, in which many factors other than the mechanisms considered intervene. A typical example of a looping effect is the relationship between a social classification and the behaviour of individuals in it. To the extent that they tend to adopt the expected behaviour, this reinforces the idea that the class is real and representative of that behaviour.

2.2. Researchers’ Characteristics and Reflexivity

FC is an academic surgeon and an experts in medical education. He has had several qualitative research experiences. The other members of the team are academic clinicians and have had a specific training in qualitative research. DP is an expert in medical ontologies, with a background in information sciences. During the preliminary discussion for the study design, no specific presumptions about the possible end result emerged.

2.3. Context and Sampling Strategy

The study was conducted in a teaching hospital, submitting the questionnaire to academic physicians of different ages and genders, senior medical students, residents. A number of primary care physicians from the city area and other cities were also involved. The authors personally proposed to the subjects to join the study, to write their answers and return the questionnaire in a post box within one week, to grant anonymity. Questionnaires were progressively numbered.
Since the questionnaire was anonymous, and the study did not imply any direct intervention on the subjects, according to Italian law an IRB ethical authorization was not needed.

2.4. Data Collection Methods

The questionnaire was designed according to the model of representation of disease proposed by Tresker [21], who developed a typology of disease formed from three factors: presence of symptoms, presence of a dysfunction (intended in Boorse’s term as an objective alteration of physiology [2]), and the concordance with diagnostic criteria. The intersection of these factors created eight categories. This proposal had the advantage of encompassing the three approaches to the definition of disease mentioned in the Introduction.
Sixteen clinical vignettes were designed, two for each category. The respondents were shown only the vignettes and not how each situation was categorized according to Tresker [21]. The responders were asked if they considered each situation as a disease or not and to motivate their choice with a free text.
Table 1 shows the eight categories and an example vignette for each.

2.5. Data Processing and Analysis, Trustworthiness

The answers to the questionnaire were transcribed in a word processor, and each medical author had a copy of the transcript. All medical authors read the transcripts and analysed them according to thematic analysis. More specifically, each author read the transcript twice, then identified the units of meaning (words or phrases that conveyed meaning of interest to the research questions) and coded them, applying a word or short phrase that expressed the meaning. Periodically, during the analysis process, the team met and compared the choices of units and codes, discussing until a common agreement was reached. These discussions were the main mechanism for strengthening trustworthiness.
After analysing about half of the texts, a common codebook was established and used to code the rest of the texts. When a new code was felt to be needed, it was noted, discussed, and added to the codebook. When no new codes emerged, saturation was declared.
Finally, FC, LG, and DP inductively collected the codes into themes and subthemes, separately and then with joint discussion to resolve any disagreements. These results were interpreted according to a critical realist approach, highlighting the CMO elements.

2.6. Ethical Issues

The survey was anonymized, and all participants were informed of the method and goal. Since there are no interventions of the subjects, the study was not subjected to an ethical approval.

3. Results

Nineteen subjects returned the questionnaire. Saturation was reached after 14 questionnaires.
Table 2. List of themes and sub-themes identified with the thematic analysis.
Table 2. List of themes and sub-themes identified with the thematic analysis.
Theme Sub-Themes
Temporal dimension of a disease Temporal nature: acute vs chronic conditions
Evolution over time of a condition
Reification of disease Disease as an objective biochemical, pathological, or functional alteration
Disease as an outcome of a cause-and-effect mechanism
Disease as a condition based on diagnostic criteria
Disease as an existential condition Disease as a general disorder of a person’s life
Disease as a specific disorder or set of symptoms
Disease as a context or setting
Disease as a motivation to action Motivation to clinical action (treatment)
Motivation to preventive action (follow up, change in life habits)
Thematic analysis showed four main themes, with ten sub-themes. The themes were: the temporal dimension of a disease, reification of disease, disease as an existential condition, disease as a motivation to action. Table 2 summarizes the themes and sub-themes, which are described in the following paragraphs with some relevant quotes from the questionnaires. Every quote has been labelled with the number of the respondent, with the letter identifying the Tresker’s category of the vignette (Table 1), and with Y/N according to the interpretation that the respondent gave of the vignette. The original data were in Italian, the reported quotes have been translated into English.

3.1. A Disease Is an Event That Occurs over Time

Direct or indirect temporal expressions were present in the motivation for the interpretation, related to the clinical nature of the problem (acute vs chronic) and to its possible evolutions. Temporal nature was mainly used to characterize the problem, whether it was considered a disease or not (an acute event): “A disease was not diagnosed as a cause of the acute event. He had an undiagnosed acute event, he was healthy” (4, G, N); “Although not recognised in its aetiology, an acute disease brought the man to exitus. He had an acute disease.” (5, G, Y)
The analysis of data also highlighted the concept of evolution over time of a health-related condition. At this proposal, one of the most illuminating quotes was “We are dynamic beings; an alteration for a short period of time cannot be called a disease.” (9, B, N). To the same extent: “The persistence of a discomfort is a reason for classifying a condition as a disease” (1, F, Y).
Finally, in the following two quotations, the risk condition was interpreted as either an element of disease or an element of non-disease, depending on the attributed evolutionary potentiality: “The woman suffers from a precancerous lesion, caused by a chronic infection. It is an objective condition with a possible degeneration” (4, B, Y); “The condition [of cervical intraepithelial neoplasia] may regress or remain stable over time” (13, B, N).

3.2. Reification of Disease: A Disease Is a Knowable Object of the World

This is the broadest theme, as it collected all mentions of an objective biochemical, pathological, or functional alteration. Instances of causal reasoning have also been included in this theme, as well as the recognition of known criteria for a specific diagnosis.
Examples of the first sub-themes were: “This woman is not ill, at present she has not any sign or symptoms, nor evidence of amyloid plaques” (3, A, N); “The patient has a cervical intraepithelial neoplasia, demonstrated with a colposcopy” (3, B, Y). Nevertheless this condition has not been recognised by another respondent as a disease, because “There is no consequence on the integrity of the self” (7, B, N) Instances of the importance of a cause-and-effect sequence were present, such as: “It seems to be a sudden acute episode, without any specific cause, in a man that was otherwise healthy” (11, G, N). Nevertheless, another respondent gave a different interpretation for the same vignette, implying a cause-and-effect sequence “The postmortem assessment documented a previous disease as the cause of the acute event” (14, G, Y). Also in vignette B, the condition was considered as a disease by the respondent who motivated the choice as “The patient has a viral infection, which caused a dysplasia” (14, B, Y).
Finally, a disease was recognised when diagnostic criteria were met, as in “This patient meet the Rome criteria for an irritable bowel syndrome” (14, F, Y)

3.3. A Disease Is an Existential Condition in a Person’s Life

Many respondents explicitly adopted the patient’s point of view in deciding if a condition was a disease or not. Subtle distinctions were made, which were classified as different sub-themes, such as the perception of a general disorder of a person’s life, a specific disorder or set of symptoms declared by the patient, or a sudden change of context or setting in the patient’s life, even without any symptom.
The same respondent reacted in a different way to vignettes A and C, using the concept of compromission of the quality of life: “At present, the condition did not alter in any way the quality of life of the woman, and she is not necessarily going to develop the disease” (11, A, N) and “The BRCA-2 mutation, beyond being an organic, genetic disfunction, compromised the overall psycho-physical state of the woman” (11, C, Y). In the same case, another respondent was even more radical, stating that: “The woman is ill, because the awareness of the mutation changed her way of looking at herself and originated a decision” (6, C, Y).
Considerations more focused on the symptoms motivated the interpretation as a disease of vignette E: “A condition of recurrent abdominal pain implies an altered health status and impairs a person's organic and psychological function.” (8, E, Y). A “persistence of the discomfort” (7, E, Y) in itself is a motivation to consider a condition as a disease.
Finally, the concept of setting and the way health information was communicated to patients were cited as elements that may or may not make a person consider that condition a disease. For example, respondents 5 wrote that “the perception of risk and probability is strongly influenced by the way in which it is communicated to the patient. This could a distressing element in a person’s life” (5, C, Y).

3.4. A disease Is a Motivation to Action for A Physician or a Patient

Some choices were motivated by the need for the physician or the patient to do something. The two classes of actions were clinical actions like treatment or preventive actions like follow up or even surgery. Examples of the these sub-themes were “The woman has a precancerous condition…objectively treatable”(4, B, Y), but the same respondent, paradoxically concluded that in the apparently similar case C (a woman with the BRCA2 mutation) the woman was not ill, because “she underwent surgery to prevent the likely onset on cancers, but she is still healthy”(4, C, N). Hence, if the medical action was treatment, the condition was interpreted as a disease, if the action was the prevention of a risk, the condition was not interpreted as a disease. Another respondent wrote “A CIN is present, that does not require a treatment” (9, B, N). Despite the different consideration about the treatability of a CIN, the two respondents agree on the fact that the need of a treatment is a landmark for the presence of a disease.
A similar paradox was present in the case of a 59-year-old man who was asymptomatic and had all the findings of a metabolic syndrome (type D). One respondent identified the man as having the criteria for a diagnosis but not ill: "This man has all the risk factors for a metabolic syndrome, but he is not actually ill. He needs to change his dietary habits and follow up.”(2, D, N).

4. Discussion

This study answered to the research questions and showed that physicians used a fairly broad set of information to decide whether a condition is a disease or not, but they used it very heterogeneously, leading to different conclusions. This finding is consistent with the result of Hoffman's study [10], which did not support the presence of a common prototypical concept of disease. Our result is also consistent with the classic distinction between the concepts of "disease" and "illness" [9], which respectively represent an objective, physician-centered or subjective, patient-centered definition of a health condition.
Further, this study showed that physicians, in reasoning about the nature of a condition, considered the temporal dimension, both as a clinical aspect and as a process in time that begins before or follows something else, not necessarily in a cause-and-effect relationship but as a risk, or a probabilistic evolution [22].
Finally, in considering the question on what purposes do doctors consider in labelling a condition as a disease, physicians seemed to take a pragmatic approach to interpreting a condition, which was not based on fixed-principle reasoning. This conclusion is consistent with Hesslow's doubt about the need for a formal definition of disease [7].

4.1. CMO Interpretation

Interpreting these results in terms of CMO configuration, the outcome is the interpretation of a situation as a disease or not and the mechanisms are the four classes of information thematized as temporal dimension, reification, existential dimension, and call to action. A fundamental tenet of critical realism is that the context can change the likelihood of a mechanism to produce an outcome. Our results showed a very heterogeneous relationship between mechanisms and type of outcome; hence our hypothesis is that the context perceived by the respondents has been the source of this heterogeneity.
A relevant element of context is the doctor-patient relationship. A characteristic and limitation inevitable of this study, like Hoffman's [10], was that physicians were surveyed about a context-free situation, with a series of written vignettes or a quantitative survey. There was neither information nor lived experience of a real situation in which a doctor and a patient meet. Many studies have shown that the physician-patient relationship affects the physician's interpretation of the patient's condition. Most studies have investigated the effect of relational context on clinical reasoning, understood as the general cognitive mechanism by which a physician makes a diagnosis [23,24], while Krimmel-Morrison et al. [25] have delved into the effect that relationship has on physicians' approaches to diagnosis and management, to building and preserving relationships with patients. The themes emerged were “Adapting clinical reasoning through the lens of patients' experiences”, “Managing tensions between clinical reasoning and relationships”, and “Clinical reasoning within patients' other influential relationships”, such as family, friends, and caregivers. It is likely that the respondents in our study implicitly and unconsciously adopted a fictitious context, and this may explain contradictions not only among different respondents, but sometimes even within the responses of the same individual: the same mechanism, in a different imagined context generated a different outcome.
Other limitations of the study were that, although varied in age, sex, professional seniority, and field of specialization, most of the respondents were from the same institution and all of them were Italian. It is possible that a different group could show further mechanisms and tendencies [26].

4.2. Educational Implications

In spite of the limitations described above, our study provided some indications for the training of undergraduate and graduate medical students.
One of the main reasons why physicians need a clear understanding of what is a disease is that pharmaceutical and technological advancements are widening the range of situations in which a doctor can intervene. Nevertheless, broadening the definition of risk factor or disease can produce overdiagnosis or overtreatment as a dangerous side effect [27]. The educational needs arise from the observation that there is not value-free possible definition of disease [28]. In their discussion of three examples of diseases (polycystic ovary syndrome, kidney chronic failure and myocardial infarction) the authors concluded that “we need theories of disease that are transparent about the values at stake, and that can be used to prevent problems that arise from indistinct boundaries.”[28 p.352].
Hence, a first commitment for medical educators must be the design of training activities in which students can be challenged with various case-based and living situations and reflect on the values at stake. Both the Tresker’s framework [21] that was used in this study, and the framework proposed by Hofmann and Eriksen [29] can be used. This last framework builds on the triad disease-illness-sickness, allowing a guided reflection on the different mechanisms in action in different contexts in real or simulated observed cases, or on paper case-based learning activities.
Another useful theoretical framework was proposed by Koufidis et al. [30], who in their scoping review identified three main conceptualizations of clinical reasoning: "reasoning as a cognitive activity," "reasoning as a contextually situated activity," and "reasoning as a socially mediated activity." These perspectives can broaden students' understanding of the reasoning process, which leads not only to a diagnosis but also to an interpretation of the patient's lived experience of discomfort, and on the consequences of each physician’s choice.
Finally, the results of the present study have shown that the method used (vignettes and related questions) can encourage reflection and make some implicit assumptions more explicit, leading the learner to have more elements to develop different interpretations of a clinical condition. This can be more effective when comparing several similar situations described in the vignettes or observed in real patients, because this can make the effect of context more apparent.

5. Conclusions

From a critical realist and systemic perspective, there is no reason to be forced to choose between a naturalist or social and normative definition of the concept of disease. If one considers the person as an open adaptive system, consisting of a body, a mind, a spirituality, a personal history, and a broad set of relationships, each subsystem is important and deserves the utmost attention. A genetic mutation that could give rise to an aggressive cancer in the future, or a biochemical alteration in an otherwise asymptomatic man, a medically unexplained symptom in a young woman, a social and economic situation that exceeds the adaptive capacity of an elderly person or an entire social group are all mechanisms that can produce an alteration in health as an outcome. This study has added some insights to the soundness of a critical realist position, which cannot be regarded as a pragmatic, hybrid approach, but is theoretically grounded.
Future research should test and assess the validity of the proposed educational activities.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, F.C. and D.P.; methodology, F.C..; validation, F.C., L.G. and D.P.; formal analysis, all authors.; investigation, all authors.; writing—original draft preparation, R.M.; writing—review and editing, F.C.; All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

according to national regulation, ethical review and approval were waived for this study because the questionnaire was anonymous and the study did not perform any intervention on the participants.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

Appendix A

SRQR checklis

References

  1. Telles Correia, D.; Stoyanov, D.; Rocha Neto, H.G. How to define today a medical disorder? Biological and psychosocial disadvantages as the paramount criteria. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice. 2022, 28, 1195–204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  2. Boorse, C. Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science. 1977, 44, 542–573. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Goosens, W.K. Values, health and medicine. Philosophy of Science. 1980, 47, 100–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  4. Wakefield, J.C. The concept of mental disorder. On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist. 1992, 47, 373–388. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  5. Ereshefsky, M. Defining 'health' and 'disease'. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci. 2009, 40, 221–227. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Livingstone-Banks, J. The case for a meta-nosological investigation of pragmatic disease definition and classification. J Eval Clin Pract. 2018, 24, 1013–1018. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  7. Hesslow, G. Do we need a concept of disease? Theor Med. 1993, 14, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  8. De Vreese, L. How to Proceed in the Disease Concept Debate? A Pragmatic Approach. J Med Philos. 2017, 42, 424–446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Boyd, KM. Disease, illness, sickness, health, healing and wholeness: exploring some elusive concepts. Med Humanit. 2000, 26, 9–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Hofmann, B. Do health professionals have a prototype concept of disease? The answer is no. Philos Ethics Humanit Med. 2017, 12, 6–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Bardes, C.L. Is Medicine Flat? Teaching and Learning in Medicine. 2007, 19, 61–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  12. Boudreau, J.D.; Cassell, E.; Fuks, A. A healing curriculum. Medical Education. 2007, 41, 1193–1201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Kumagai, A.K. Beyond "Dr. Feel-Good": A Role for the Humanities in Medical Education. Acad Med. 2017, 92, 1659–1660. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  14. Kumagai, A.K. A Conceptual Framework for the Use of Illness Narratives in Medical Education. Academic Medicine. 2008, 83, 653. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  15. O'Brien, B.C.; Harris, I.B.; Beckman, T.J.; Reed, D.A.; Cook, D.A. Standards for reporting qualitative research: a synthesis of recommendations. Acad Med. 2014, 89, 1245–1251. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  16. Braun, V.; Clarke, V. Using thematic analysis in psychology. Qualitative Research in Psychology. 2006, 3, 77–101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Vincent, S.; O’Mahoney, J. Critical Realism and Qualitative Research: An Introductory Overview. In The SAGE Handbook of Qualitative Business and Management Research Methods; Vincent, S., O’Mahoney, J., Eds.; SAGE Publications Ltd: London (UK), 2024. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Scott, D. Critical Realism and Empirical Research Methods in Education. Journal of Philosophy of Education. 2006, 39, 633–646. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Porter, S.; O'Halloran, P. The use and limitation of realistic evaluation as a tool for evidence-based practice: a critical realist perspective. Nurs Inq. 2012, 19, 18–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Maturana, H.; Varela, F.J. Autopoiesis and cognition. The realization of living; Reidel Publishing Co.: Dordecht (Holland), 1980. [Google Scholar]
  21. Tresker, S. A typology of clinical conditions. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci. 2020, 83, 101291. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Consorti, F.; Torre, D.; Luzi, D.; Pecoraro, F.; Ricci, F.; Tamburis, O. The challenge of clinical reasoning in chronic multimorbidity: time and interactions in the Health Issues Network model. Diagnosis (Berl). 2023, 10, 348–352. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Ashoorion, V.; Liaghatdar, M.J.; Adibi, P. What variables can influence clinical reasoning? Journal of Research in Medical Sciences 2012, 17, 1170–1175. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
  24. Konopasky, A.; Artino, A.R.; Battista, A.; Ohmer, M.; Hemmer, P.A.; Torre, D.; Ramani, D.; Merrienboer, J.; van Teunissen, P.W.; McBee, E.; Ratcliffe, T.; Durning, S.J. Understanding context specificity: The effect of contextual factors on clinical reasoning. Diagnosis 2020, 7, 257–264. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Krimmel-Morrison, J.D.; Watsjold, B.K.; Berger, G.N.; Bowen, J.L.; Ilgen, J.S. 'Walking together': How relationships shape physicians' clinical reasoning. Medical education 2024. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  26. Lynch, E.; Medin, D. Explanatory models of illness: A study of within-culture variation. Cognitive Psychology 2006, 53, 285–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  27. Bandovas, J.P.; Leal, B.; Reis-de-Carvalho, C.; Sousa, D.C.; Araújo, J.C.; Peixoto, P.; Henriques, S.O.; Vaz Carneiro, A. Broadening risk factor or disease definition as a driver for overdiagnosis: A narrative review. Journal of Internal Medicine 2022, 291, 426–437. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Doust, J.; Jean Walker, M.; Rogers, W.A. Current Dilemmas in Defining the Boundaries of Disease. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 2017, 42, 350–366. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Hofmann, B.M.; Eriksen, H.M. The concept of disease: Ethical challenges and relevance to dentistry and dental education. European Journal of Dental Education 2001, 5, 2–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  30. Koufidis, C.; Manninen, K.; Nieminen, J.; Wohlin, M.; Silén, C. Unravelling the polyphony in clinical reasoning research in medical education. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice. 2021, 27, 438–450. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Table 1. The eight categories and examples of clinical vignettes. In bold, information that is consistent with the factors according to Tresker's typology [21]. The elements that characterize each situation are in bold.
Table 1. The eight categories and examples of clinical vignettes. In bold, information that is consistent with the factors according to Tresker's typology [21]. The elements that characterize each situation are in bold.
A. Asymptomatic person, without dysfunction, and not meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
A healthy 35-year-old woman, early Alzheiemer family history (mother, with onset at age 50). Genetic testing suggested a predisposition for disease development. Periodic neuroimaging examinations were recommended so as to highlight pre-symptomatic beta-amyloid accumulation.
B. Asymptomatic person, without dysfunction, but meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
A healthy 25-year-old woman. She had periodic Pap tests, the last of which demonstrated "atypia of uncertain significance." The viral DNA search was positive, and a colposcopy demonstrated the presence of a cervical intraepithelial neoplasia (CIN), for which no therapeutic indication was placed but only follow-up.
C. Asymptomatic person, with dysfunction, not meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
A 41-year-old woman with a maternal history of breast cancer based on the BRCA2 mutation. After genetic testing, the woman was also found to have a BRCA2 mutation. PE, breast ultrasound, mammogram, MRI, gynaecological examination, and trans-vaginal ultrasound were negative; CA125 was normal. After 18 months of follow up, the woman agreed to undergo bilateral mastectomy and hystero-annexectomy.
D. Asymptomatic person, with dysfunction, meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
A 25-year-old woman, a nurse on regular duty, was used to act out self-injurious behaviours (scratches on legs) in private, which she hid under her uniform from colleagues and patients A psychiatrist matched the criteria for a diagnosis of schizoid syndrome. Except for some mild mood swings, which she controls pharmacologically, at present she has no problems at work.
E. Symptomatic person, without dysfunction, and not meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
A 50-year-old man with recurrent abdominal pain in the right lower quadrant started about a year ago and no change in bowel habits. Appendectomy 10 years ago. PE negative for parietal hernias, WBC normal, CT scan of abdomen and pelvis negative for bowel and renal changes, no lymphadenopathy.
F. Symptomatic person, without dysfunction, meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
A 25-year-old woman with recurrent abdominal pain and increased bowel movement with soft stools in the past 6 weeks. No weight loss; PE not significant; negative faecal test for pathogenic bacteria, parasites, test for celiac disease, and calprotectin. Negative abdominal ultrasound. Despite a diet correction, the disorder persists. The woman reports having a series of job interviews in progress.
G. Symptomatic person, with dysfunction, not meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
A 70-year-old man in good health complains of the sudden onset of acute, diffuse postprandial abdominal pain.In the ER, the man is agitated, confused at times, his abdomen is diffusely tender, but without defensive contractures. Blood pressure 220/110. Despite treatment initiated, within hours, exitus occurs. Autopsy documents extensive bowel infarction that had not been suspected or diagnosed.
H. Symptomatic person, with dysfunction, meeting diagnostic criteria for a disease.
84-year-old man with a history of COPD. The man is confused, temperature 38.7 °C, dyspnoea, productive cough, saturimetry = 88%
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.
Copyright: This open access article is published under a Creative Commons CC BY 4.0 license, which permit the free download, distribution, and reuse, provided that the author and preprint are cited in any reuse.
Prerpints.org logo

Preprints.org is a free preprint server supported by MDPI in Basel, Switzerland.

Subscribe

© 2024 MDPI (Basel, Switzerland) unless otherwise stated