2. Characterization of Measurement Contexts
Many fundamental investigations of quantum statistics start with the two dimensional Hilbert space of a logical qubit. The physical analogy is a spin-1/2 system, where every direction in space is a potential measurement basis. It is difficult to formulate a logical relation between the different measurement contexts, since no two measurements can be performed jointly and each measurement outcome belongs to only one possible measurement context. The situation changes when a three dimensional Hilbert space is considered. It is now possible to construct a much wider range of possible measurements, and two different measurement contexts can share the same measurement outcome. The Kochen-Specker theorem uses such relations to investigate the statistical relations between incompatible measurements, demonstrating that the relation between different measurement contexts cannot be described by uncertainty limited classical statistics [
5]. In the most simple scenario, five different measurement contexts are related to each other by shared measurement outcomes in a three dimensional Hilbert space [
6,
7,
8,
9]. As shown in
Figure 1, the symmetry of this scenario can be illustrated by a pentagram, where each measurement context is represented by a triangle and the shared outcomes form a pentagon at the center. Note that this representation is a more complete version of the graph derived in [
24]. I am using the same terminology, with the context
at the top, the contexts
and
sharing the outcomes 1 and 2 at their respective sides, and the contexts
and
at the bottom, joined by the shared outcome
f.
The conventional formulation of quantum theory forces us to chose a basis in which to represent the states and the operators. This can cause serious misunderstandings, since each basis only represents one of the five possible measurements. It is important to remember that the physics of a quantum system should be independent of the basis chosen to describe it. Although
Figure 1 correctly identifies the shared measurement outcomes, it remains unclear what the relations between the other outcomes are. In fact, quantum theory defines the relation between two measurement contexts in terms of a unitary transformation, and in the case of the five contexts shown in
Figure 1, the transformations between adjacent contexts involves a transformation in the two-dimenional subspace orthogonal to the shared context [
24]. As I have shown recently, this relation can be illustrated by a three-path interferomer, where the measurement outcomes of the different contexts are represented by the paths along which a single quantum particle propagates through the interferometer [
25]. The transformation between adjacent contexts is then implemented by beam splitters that control the overlap between the quantum states representing the paths.
Figure 2 shows the interferometer. Each of the five beam splitters can be identified with the path parallel to it, corresponding to the shared measurement outcome of the contexts before and after the beam splitter. As was shown in [
24,
25], selecting any two beam splitter reflectivities will determine the other three. An option that is particularly easy to analyze is obtained when
, which results in the remaining reflectities being given by
and
.
What can be said about the relation between different measurement contexts? The identification of measurement contexts with the different stages of single-particle propagation in a three-path interferometer illustrates this relation by associating measurement outcomes with physical paths. A non-contextual hidden variable model would then assign a specific path through the interferometer to each particle. Since the input context
is perfectly recovered at the output ports, paths originating from input 1 must end up in output 1 and so forth, leaving a total of eleven distinct possibilities for the propagation of the particle.
Table 1 illustrates the eleven paths by assigning a sequence of Hilbert space vectors to each of them. As the table shows, two path segments
are sufficient to define each of the paths, except for the path composed of the five segments that are unique to each context, which is therefore labeled
. The quantum mechanical relations that replace the sequence of paths in the Hilbert space formalism are inner products of the state vectors that represent the measurement outcomes of the different contexts [
24]. Although quantum contextuality shows that quantum states cannot be represented by positive valued probability distributions over the eleven paths in
Table 1, it should be possible to find a quasi-probability representation of the density matrix that relates directly to these 11 paths. It has already been noted elsewhere that Kirkwood-Dirac quasiprobabilities are ideally suited for this purpose [
25,
26,
27]. In the following, I will develop an expansion of the density matrix that can serve as a starting point for a detailed investigation of the relations between the five measurement contexts described by the Hilbert space formalism.
4. Complete Expansions of Arbitrary States
The completeness relation in Eq.(
1) can be used to express any pure state
as a superposition of the three states
, where the coefficients are given by inner products with the states
,
It should be noted that non-orthogonal expansions reveal a fundamental problem with the notion that each of the components represents a possible “reality”. The coefficients of the expansion are not zero when the state is orthogonal to that component, but instead refer to a different set of states. This means that expansions of states orthogonal to one or two of the components will include non-zero contributions of those components. The problem is best illustrated by the expansion of the state
,
Destructive interference between
and
ensures that
, and destructive interference between
and
ensures that
. This requires non-trivial relations between the inner products,
As this example shows, all of the inner products are related to each other by the orthogonality relations between the five different measurement contexts [
24]. To simplify the relations, it is useful to introduce a specific numerical example. As noted in [
24], the example can be defined by the expansion of the states
and
in the
basis. It is therefore convenient to chose equal superpositions,
All other superpositions can then be derived using the orthogonality conditions of the relations between the five measurement contexts. Most notably,
is orthogonal to both
and
, so the representation of the state in the
basis is necessarily given by
With these definitions, the expansion of
in Eq.(
7) is given by
Note that the physics represented by the state cannot depend on its representation. The characterization of an unknown state should not be based on the components of a representation, but on the coefficients of the expansion and any physical meaning that they may have that is independent of the expansion in which they are used.
The coefficients of the non-orthogonal expansion of quantum states given by Eq.(
6) describe coherences between non-orthogonal states. Such coherences can be represented by Kirkwood-Dirac quasi probabilities,
As mentioned before, the Kirkwood-Dirac quasi probabilities describe the relation between the quantum statistics of
and
in terms of the weak values of
post-selected in
[
16,
17]. In the following, I will refer to them as KD terms. When the non-orthogonal expansion of Eq.(
6) is applied to a density operator
, the coefficients of the expansion can be expressed by a combination of probabilities and KD terms,
The expansion combines the probabilities of the three outcomes 1, f and with KD terms for all three combinations, , and . These six elements correspond to the diagonal and off-diagonal terms of a density matrix, where the coherences are replaced by complex quasi probabilities that assign a joint statistical weight to each pair of outcomes.
The expansion given in Eq.(
13) did not require any normalization of the density operator
. It is therefore possible to derive an additional relation between the six coefficients using the condition
. For example, it is possible to express the probability of
as
A normalized quantum state is completely determined by the two probabilites
,
, and the three KD terms
,
,
. Experimentally, KD terms can be determined by weak measurements or by a variety of other methods involving quantum interferences [
16,
17,
18,
19,
20,
21]. Eqs.(
13) and (
14) show that the statistics of all possible measurements can be expressed by linear combinations of these five coefficients and the normalization. In the following, we will take a look at how this expansion of the quantum state relates different contexts to each other.
5. Reconstruction of a Kirkwood-Dirac Distribution
A Kirkwood-Dirac distribution describes the relation between two different measurement contexts in the form of a complex joint probability of all possible combinations of outcomes. If the inner products of outcomes from different contexts are non-zero, the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution of these contexts is a complete representation of the quantum state [
16,
17,
28,
29]. However, this procedure cannot be applied to any of the five contexts, since at least two of the outcomes from different contexts will be orthogonal to each other. It is therefore not surprising that the expansion in Eq.(
13) combines outcomes from all five contexts. The selection of the specific expansion given by Eq.(
1) defines expansion coefficients associated with the path
in
Table 1. It is possible to relate these coefficients to a complete Kirkwood-Dirac distribution for the contexts defined by the unique outcomes
and
. This Kirkwood-Dirac distribution has a total of eight non-zero elements, as shown in
Table 2. Five of these elements are needed to determine the five coefficients of the expansion in Eq.(
13). It is conventient to use the five coefficients marked in red, since the coefficients can then be determined by simple sums. The probabilities
and
are marginals of the distribution,
The remaining two coefficients are given by KD terms that involve
. Since
is orthogonal to
,
does not include the contribution of
to
. The same holds true for
and
. The two remaining KD terms in the expansion are therefore given by
Only five of the eight elements of the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution for the contexts and are needed to completely define an arbitrary quantum state. The relation between the contexts represented by the orthogonality of and thus simplifies the characterization of an unknown state.
The Kirkwood-Dirac distribution is a helpful representation of the relations between two different contexts. It is therefore interesting to investigate how Eq.(
13) relates the five coefficients that appear in the expansion to the remaining three elements of the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution in
Table 2. The easiest way to find the result is to consider the probabilities of
and 2,
These marginals of the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution determine the KD terms
and
from the elements marked in red in
Table 2. The remaining element
can be determined from the normalization of the distribution. Since
,
and
form the orthogonal basis of a third context, it is also possible to determine
from the probability of
as given in Eq.(
14). The three probabilities are related to the elements of the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution by
The remaining elements of the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution can then be expressed by the five KD terms used in the reconstruction of the quantum state,
These equations represent a set of universal rules that relate the elements of a single Kirkwood-Dirac distribution to each other. It is worth looking at these rules in detail, to figure out what kind of statistical relations they express.
The most obvious reason why there should be a relation between the elements is the normalization of the distribution. Probabilities attributed to the five elements used in the reconstruction will be missing from the three additional elements. If all of the elements used in the reconstruction are zero, the state is
and the three additional elements are
,
, and
. It is interesting to observe that there is no degree of freedom left. There is only one state with
. Eq.(
19) then defines the necessary uncertainty of this state in terms of a joint probability of the remaining outcomes
and
. We can also consider cases where there is only one non-zero element among the five elements used in the reconstruction of the state. Most obviously, this is the case for
, where
, and for
, where
. In both cases, a contribution proportional to the non-zero element is subtracted from two of the three elements in Eq.(
19), leaving only one additional element with a non-zero value. Naturally, this element obtains exactly the value needed for a total probability of one,
for
and
for
. It is worth noting that a value of
greater than
would result in a negative value of
, indicating a strict limit to the concentration of quasi probabilities in a single KD term. A lower value of
is possible, since it corresponds to a mixed state of
and
. The reason for the upper limit of
is that the reconstructed state would be a non-positive state - specifically, a mixture of
and
with a negative contribution from
.
Finally, it may be instructive to consider states with particularly high probabilities of 1 and
f, since the reconstruction method and the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution put special emphasis on these two outcomes. For
, the KD-terms are
,
and
, while
. As expected, Eq.(
19) then states that the remaining three elements of the distribution are zero. Any attempt to re-distribute probabilities between the three non-zero elements will result in a re-distribution of a total probability of zero between
and
, resulting in at least one negative probability. Eq.(
19) thus allows only one probability distribution of 1, 2 and 3 for
. The same holds true for the state
, where the only possible probability distribution is
,
and
, while
.
Since we are interested in the relations between the two contexts in the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution, we can now take a look at a state that achieves high probabilities for both 1 and
f simultaneously. Since such a state closely approximates the trajectory
, I will refer to it as the state
. To keep the numerics simple, let us consider the superposition
This state has
, so that it can be represented as a superposition of
and
. The interference between these two components is constructive, adding a probability of
to the probabilities associated with the expansion coefficients. The state can also be written as
When written in this form, it is easy to derive the probabilities for any of the five measurement contexts. For , we get contributions of 1 from all operators except for , where the contribution is . The total probability is therefore . Similarly, results in contributions of 1 except for , where the contribution is 1/3. The total probability is . In classical statistics, these probabilities would suggest a joint probability of 1 and f of at least , obtained under the assumption that the system is always either in f or in 1. However, the corresponing KD term is only . This is possible because negative values appear in the KD terms that are neither related to 1 nor to f.
Table 3 shows the complete Kirkwood-Dirac distribution of the state
. According to Eq.(
19), an increase in
will result in a decrease of
and
. In the present case, we find that
and
. The third KD term in Eq.(
19) has a positive value of
. Eq.(
19) shows that these three values correspond an addition of
to
compared with a situation where all three KD terms are initially zero, the situation obtained for any incoherent mixture of
and
. The superposition state
thus corresponds to a mixture of
and
with an addition of
to
. Specifically, a mixture of
times
and
times
has the same values for
,
,
and
as
, but all of the remaining probability are found in
. The coherence between
and
increases the value of
by
, and this increase in
results in increase of
times
or
in
a decrease of
times
or
in
, and a decrease of
times
or
in
. Eq.(
19) thus shows that negative KD terms are needed to achieve high values in other KD terms. The analysis in this section has shown that these relations are already obtained when only two contexts are related to each other. This is especially interesting because the Kochen-Specker theorem assigns a cyclic and symmetric role to all five contexts, as illustrated in
Figure 1. In the following, I will take a look at the inequality violation used to demonstrate contextuality in the present scenario and use it as a starting point for a formulation of cyclic relations between KD terms that correspond to non-contextual hidden variable theories for the five contexts.
6. Inequality Violations and Cyclic Relations between All Five Contexts
Non-contextual hidden variable models assume that the outcomes of all measurements are pre-determined for each individual system. For the three-path interferometer in
Figure 2, this means that each particle follows a specific path through the five contexts, corresponding to the paths shown in
Table 1. If this is indeed the case, it is possible to identify extremal values of collective properties that define inequalities for the experimentally observable statistics. In the well-studied case of the five contexts defined here, the maximal number of shared outcomes that a path may include is two. This means that two is the maximal value we should obtain if we sum the probabilities of all shared outcomes [
8],
It is well known that this inequality can be violated, and various formulations of this paradox have been discussed [
8,
9]. Here, our goal is to relate the paradox to the KD terms that describe the relations between different measurement contexts.
In the tomographic reconstruction considered above, we have direct access to
and
, as shown in Eq.(
15).
and
are given in Eq.(
17). Since only the sum of
and
is needed, it is sufficient to refer to
in Eq.(
14) to obtain
This leaves only the probability
. Using Eq.(
13)and Eq.(
14), this probability can be given as
The sum of all five probabilities is then given by
An inequality violation is observed whenever the KD terms used in the reconstruction of the state satisfy
Despite its negative KD terms,
does not satisfy this requirement and therefore fails to violate the inequality in Eq.(
22). This is not surprising, since the probability of
in
is zero, and the remaining probabilities in the sum
can be divided into pairs from the same context. In general, the inequality given by Eq.(
22) cannot be violated when one of the five probabilities is zero. As pointed out in [
8], a state that optimally achieves a violation can be obtained by superpositions of all five states representing the outcomes that contribute to the inequality, simultaneously achieving very similar probabilities for all five outcomes. A state that is close to the maximal inequality violation is given by [
37]
The tomographic data for this state is given by
The value of the sum obtained with this data is , violating the inequality by . The individual probabilities are , and .
Eq.(
26) indicates that the violation of the non-contextual inequality in Eq.(
22) can be explained by the negative
terms of the paths
and
. The tomographic data of Eq.(
28) thus explains the inequality violation in terms of its negative KD terms. However, Eq.(
22) does not require negative KD terms for its violation, and the specific selection of the tomographic data hides the fact that all five contexts play an equivalent role in the violation of the inequality. It is therefore desirable to derive a more complete form of the inequality, where the role of negativity and its relation to generalized probabilities as discussed in [
10,
11] is more apparent. In the case of the
state, we would expect negative KD terms for all paths with four segments in
Table 1. In addition to the paths
and
, these are the paths
,
and
. If we simply complete the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution, we get the terms
,
and
. According to
Table 1, each of these combinations of outcomes occurs in two of the eleven paths. The Hilbert space algebra confirms that the KD terms can be expressed in terms of the corresponding sums,
All of the KD terms defined by pairs of outcomes can be determined using Eq.(
12). The KD term
of the path through all five unique outcomes needs a different definition. The general definition can be obtained by referring to the normalization of the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution,
This equation can be simplified by summarizing the KD terms associated with 1 and 2, for
Independently, the fact that
projects states into the Hilbert space spanned by
and
, while
does the same for
and
can be used to derive a very similar expression for
,
Based on these relations, a conveniently symmetric definition of
is
In general, contributes to all KD terms defined by pairs of outcomes that are unique to two different contexts.
Eq.(
30) shows that all quantum states can be characterized by a quasi probability distribution given by eleven KD terms that correspond to the 11 possible paths through the five contexts shown in
Table 1. If all KD terms are positive, these eleven terms can be interpreted as a probability distribution of the possible joint assignment of measurement outcomes to all five contexts. The eleven KD terms can thus establish a link between quantum statistics and hidden variable theories. However, quantum theory introduces additional relations between the eleven KD terms. Since only five KD terms are needed to characterize the quantum state completely, there should be a set of six relations that determine the remaining six KD terms as a function of these five. One of these relations is the normalization, and this relation can be used to determine
once the other five KD terms have been determined. The remaining five relations can be derived from Eq.(
3), where each KD term is given by the expectation value of the operator
according to
Eq.(
3) thus defines a set of deterministic relations between the KD terms that express a distribution of statistical weights over the possible quasi realities obtained by assigning a specific measurement outcome to each context. These fundamental constraints satisfied by the KD terms of all possible input states are given by
The KD terms in each line correspond to paths that do not share the same measurement outcome in any of the five contexts. It is therefore possible to assign exactly one KD term to each outcome in each of the five lines. For outcomes that are shared by two contexts, this results in three non-zero KD terms, e.g. , and for . Since the sum is one, the eleventh KD term is . On the other hand, outcomes that are unique to only one context have a total of five non-zero KD terms. For the state , these are the four positive KD terms , , , , and the fifth negative KD term .
The appearance of a negative KD term in states associated with a specific measurement outcome may seem surprising, since such a state is related to the other contexts directly by its inner products with the outcomes of those contexts. Indeed,
is somewhat special, since it cannot be derived from a single weak value and does not appear in any Kirkwood-Dirac distribution of only two measurement contexts. It can be confirmed that, for all outcomes that are unique to only one context, the value of this KD term is
. The origin of this value is found in a Bargmann invariant defined by the Hilbert space vectors representing the five outcomes that are unique to each context,
In principle, it is possible to show that Eq.(
33) identifies this Bargmann invariant with
for the states
,
,
,
and
. However, it might be more useful to show that the value of
must be the same for each of these states. This can be done by determining
for a maximally mixed state,
. For that state,
and
. Specifically,
is negative because
. Since
is zero for each state shared by two contexts, the negative value of the maximally mixed state must correspond to one third of the value of the state unique to that context for each decomposition of the mixed state into a mixture of states representing the measurement outcomes of any of the three contexts.
In general, all quantum states can be described by the 11 quasi probabilities of the different paths through the contexts. However, even mixed states tend to have negative KD values. The only states that result in positive non-contextual probabilities are states that can be expressed as mixtures of the five outcomes that are shared by two contexts. Significantly, this does not include the maximally mixed state
with its negative KD term of
. The violation of non-contextuality as given by Eq.(
22) requires a very specific combination of negative KD terms. To find these, we can make use of the correspondence between KD terms and classical paths through the contexts. Path
has no shared outcomes, paths
,
,
,
,
have one shared outcome each, and the remaining five paths have two shared outcomes. The average number of shared outcomes can then be found by subtracting the KD terms of the paths with less than two shared outcomes from an initial value of two,
This expression for the probability sum
shows that a violation of inequality (
22) is impossible unless some of the KD terms given are negative. As suggested by Spekkens in [
10], the origin of contextuality paradoxes can be traced to negative KD terms that suppress the contributions of paths with one shared outcome or none at all. Importantly, Kochen-Spekker scenarios require a joint probability characterizing more than two contexts. The eleven KD terms introduced here achieve this for all five contexts, even though each KD term is defined by only two outcomes. This is the significance of
Table 1. Quantum contextuality actually provides an extended probability theory that corresponds to the assignment of outcomes to all five contexts at the same time.
7. Contextual Fluctuations
The eleven KD terms represent a distribution of joint statistical weights for all five contexts, where each KD term represents a specific combination of outcomes for each of the five contexts, corresponding to one of the paths in
Table 1. Like other quasi probabilities, this multi-context Kirkwood-Dirac distribution seeks to bridge the gap between a naive realism that assumes a co-existence of the measurement outcomes along a path and an equally naive anti-realism that simply assumes that there is no connection between the outcomes of different measurements. To guard ourselves against both misconceptions, we should accept that the 11 element Kirkwood-Dirac distribution describes a deterministic relation between the five different measurement contexts that cannot be reconciled with any joint reality of outcomes. To understand the concept of quantum contextuality better, we need to focus on the fact that only one measurement context describes the reality of an actual event. Measurement probabilities are obtained from sums of KD terms for this event, and all of these sums will necessarily be positive. Negative KD terms can never be observed in isolation, since their experimentally observable effects appear only in sums where the contributions from positive KD terms outweigh those from the negative ones. Quantum contextuality suggests that the reality observed in one measurement context is fundamentally different from the reality observed in a different measurement context. However, the KD terms
still describe a well-defined relation between the outcomes
a and
b. We should consider this in more detail - if the relation between
a and
b is valid when we measure
a, then the measurement of
a determines the reality of
b as well. The set of values provided by the KD terms thus describes a contextual reality of
b conditioned by the directly observed outcome
a.
The problem that prevents us from understanding quantum mechanics is that we identify physical properties with their eigenvalue, clinging to the believe that these eigenvalues are a complete and exclusive set of possibilities from which we can construct an objective reality. However, this is a very unlikely interpretation of the formalism. Instead, we should consider a much wider variety of possibilities, where the outcomes of the context
a are related to contextual realities of outcomes
b that are different from the limited options of the binary yes or no associated with the eigenvalues of the projectors [
38,
39,
40,
41]. We need to accept that the values of projectors associated with other measurement outcomes can be different from 0 or 1. Is it possible to make intuitive sense of such a possibility? Perhaps a change of terminology is needed - “truth value” applies only to actual observations. Here, I will use the term “outcome value,” or more specifically, “contextual outcome value”. It is easiest to visualize this change by considering the case of a single particle propagating along paths. As has already been demonstrated experimentally [
39], a particle is genuinely de-localized between different paths when these paths interfere in the output. We can now generalize this result to all quantum systems by describing the conditional reality of outcomes
b as a physical distribution of the total outcome value of 1 over the outcomes
b.
The concept of a context dependent reality can be illustrated using the relations between measurement contexts described by the KD terms. Each measurement context has three outcomes, two of which are shared with other contexts and one of which is unique to that context. The measurement probabilities are given by sums of three KD terms for each of the shared outcomes, and by a sum of the remaining five KD terms for the outcome unique to this context. For instance, the probabilities of the context
are given by
Each measurement outcome assigns a truth value of 1 to one of the three outcomes, and a truth value of 0 to the others. These truth values correspond to eigenvalues of the projection operators
of the measurement context. Quantum mechanics strongly suggests that we should not assign such eigenvalues to unobserved measurement outcomes. Instead, weak values can be used to relate the outcomes
b to a post-selected outcome of the measurement context
a [
25,
38,
39]. Using the terminology above, these weak values are the contextual outcome values of
b in the context of
a. If the measurement outcome
a is obtained with a probability of
, the contextual outcome value
of an outcome
b is given by
Technically,
corresponds to the complex conditional probabilities discussed in some of my previous work [
28,
29], where the status of the Kirkwood-Dirac distribution as a symmetric quasi probability of two measurement contexts was emphasized. However, contextuality suggests that we need to abandon the idea of a truth value of zero or one for outcomes that are not observed in their own context - or “eigencontext” as I shall refer to in the following.
If the contextual outcome values
are considered as individual values of the observable represented by the projector
, it is possible to define the fluctuations of this value in the context of
a by assigning the probabilities
to the corresponding outcome values
. The dependence of
on
a thus represents the fluctuations of
b in the context
a. Since the average value of
is equal to the probability
, the fluctuation of
is given by
As shown in a number of previous works, the fluctuations of weak values over a complete set of post-selected outcomes are equal to the uncertainty of the corresponding observable for pure state inputs [
38,
42,
43]. For the contextual values
,
In the limit of pure states and precise measurements, the contextual fluctuations of the outcome values are equal to the fluctuations of the truth value observed in a direct measurement of the corresponding context. This is strong evidence that the values describe a context dependent reality.
To connect this analysis with quantum tomography, it is necessary to consider the role of the initial state in the definition of contextual fluctuations. If the state is a pure state, it is characterized by a deterministic statement corresponding to a certain prediction of a measurement outcome. Whether this prediction is explicit of not, it has an effect on the outcome values. An example may help to explain this dependence. Let us consider the state
. Its eleven KD terms are given by
As explained above, the KD term
of this state is negative. We can therefore expect to find negative outcome values for some of the outcomes when the measurement context is not the eigencontext of that outcome. For instance, the values
of the outcome
and their probabilities in the context
are given by
Note that I have included the initial state in the conditions that determine the value
. This is intended as a reminder of the physical meaning of these values. The combination of state preparation
and measurement outcome
m completely describes the physical reality of the system. The value
for this physical reality is determined by these conditions, leaving no uncertainty in the value of the projector
. We can confirm this assumption by finding the fluctuation of
. In every measurement context, the average value of
in the state
is equal to the probability of
,
. The fluctuations of
in
are given by
The fluctuations obtained for the context
are the same as the fluctuations obtained in the eigencontext of
, even though the outcome values themselves are very different. This is a strong indication that the individual realities associated with this fluctuation depend on the measurement context. In its eigencontext, the outcome
simply has a low probability. In the context
, the main contribution to the expectation value of
originates from the most likely outcome of 2, for which the outcome value of
is
, much smaller than a truth value of 1, but still three times larger than the average. The negative outcome value of
for the less likely outcome of 3 is needed to achieve the same average and the same fluctuations as the eigencontext of
. This is similar to the negative presence of a particle in a two-path interferometer that was reported in the neutron interference experiment in [
39]. In general, negative contextual outcome values are observed when the probability of the observed outcome is low because of destructive interference between outcomes of the unobserved context. The quantum formalism assigns precise conditional values to these unobserved outcomes, providing a context dependent description of the quantum fluctuations of
in the input state
. Weak values and KD terms represent deterministic relations that allow statements about the values of unobserved physical properties. In the case of projectors, negative values indicate a particularly strong deterministic suppression of contributions from this outcome.
The initial state defines averages and fluctuations. It does not define outcome values and probabilities. These can only be determined when the context is fixed. It is therefore interesting to take a look at states that seek to minimize the uncertainties if outcomes in all five contexts. As discussed above, the state
achieves this by enhancing the KD term that corresponds to the path
through the five contexts.
Table 3 already shows five of the eleven KD terms for this state. The complete set of eleven KD terms can be obtained from the table by making use of the observation that the
state has
. Therefore, each of the eight elements in the table appear as one of the eleven KD terms, while the remaing three KD terms have values of zero. The complete set of KD terms is given by
The state
satisfies the conditions given by Eq. (
35) by compensating the enhancement of
above its eigenstate value of
with two negative KD terms,
and
. Note that the paths
and
represented by these two KD terms do not share any outcome with
in
Table 1. This means that simultaneous control of five contexts is achieved at least in part by suppressing joint contributions of the unintended outcomes. We expect to see this effect more clearly in the relation between observed outcomes and contextual outcome values.
We can now consider the statistics of outcome values for
f,
and
in the measurement context
. The probabilities of each outcome and the contextual distribution of the total outcome value of 1 over
f,
and
are given by
The first thing that should be noted is the way in which the high average of
for the outcome
f is obtained. Instead of assigning a high value to the most likely outcome of 1, the Hilbert space formalism determines a value of only
(
of the average of
) to this outcome. Oppositely, the less likely outcomes 2 and 3 have a contextual value of
for
f, exceeding the eigenvalue limit of 1 of the projector. This is a direct consequence of the relations in Eq.(
35), where the high value of
is achieved by suppressing joint contributions of
and
. This suppression is directly visible in the negative outcome values of
for outcome 2, and for
for outcome 3. If the distributions of outcome values are viewed together, the concentration of outcome values on
f can be observed for each of the outcomes, but it is much weaker for the most likely outcome of 1 and extremely enhanced by outcome values outside the eigenvalue range for the less likely outcomes of 2 and 3.
As noted above, the statistical fluctuations of the outcome values are all equal to the corresponding truth value fluctuations of the eigencontext statistics given by the probabilities of
,
and
. This can be confirmed by considering the differences between the outcome values and the average values represented by the probabilities,
The statistical fluctuations of the outocomes f, and observed in their eigencontext are fully reproduced by the statistics of the outcome values associated with the outcomes 1, 2 and 3. No additional randomness is required - the fluctuation of the outcomes in the context has the same physical origin as the fluctuation of the outcomes in the context .
As shown above, the inequality violations usually associated with quantum contextuality is a natural consequence of the dependence of outcome values on the measurement context, where negative contextual outcome values appear as fluctuations associated with low probability outcomes. Inequality violations can be achieved when a specific set of KD terms is negative, as shown in Eq.(
37). In the case of the state
, five of the six
terms contributing to the inequality violation are negative. The complete set of eleven KD terms can be obtained from the five terms in Eq.(
28) and the relations in Eq.(
35). The results read
The value of the sum
is given by
The inequality (
22) is violated because the negative KD terms for paths with one shared outcome outweigh twice the positive KD term of the path with no shared outcome. The
state is nearly symmetric in the five contexts, with maximal suppression of the outcomes unique to each context. For the measurement context
, the measurement probabilities and the contextual values
,
and
are given by
The first thing to note regarding the dependence of the contextual values on the measurement outcomes is the dominance of suppression effects over enghancement effects. For an outcome of 1, the contextual values of f and are nearly equal, but the contextual value of is negative. For an outcome of 3, the value of is greater than one, but the value of is also much larger than its average of . More impressive is the suppression of the value of f to , especially since the average value of f is . For the outcome 2, the value of is the eigenvalue of zero, but it is worth noting that the conditional values of f and are the same. Each outcome has high values for two of the three outcomes, even though the statistics of these outcome values fully explain the input state uncertainties, leaving no room for any uncertainties in the conditional values themselves. Negative contextual values describe the deterministic relations between different contexts as extreme anti-correlations, exceeding the limits based on the assumption that the maximal correlation is a joint reality represented by a conditional value of one for a specific outcome and a value of zero for the two others.
It is important to remember that a non-contextual reality can only assign truth values of zero or one to each outcome, whether the outcome is actually observed in the measurement or not. The operator formalism contradicts this assumption on a seemingly technical level, by assigning weak values defined by the combination of deterministic input state properties with the additional information provided by the measurement context. The statistical analysis of the distribution over weak values for a specific measurement shows that weak values represent the same uncertainties also described by the eigenvalues, even though the individual values are different. In the case of the outcome
f, the average value defined by the initial condition
is
in every context. In the eigencontext, a value of 1 is obtained with a probability of
and a value of zero is obtained else. In the context
, a value of
is obtained with a probability of
, and a value of
is obtained with a probability of
. The fluctuations of the two contexts are the same,
The negative contextual value associated with a rare outcome of 3 describes the fluctuations in terms of sudden deviations from a value much closer to the average than the truth values of zero and one. Both the values and the distributions of quantum fluctuations depend on the measurement context, even though their total magnitude is completely detemined by the initial state.
The outcome
has an average value of
, which corresponds to a maximal uncertainty of
in any context. Since the outcome
is orthogonal to
, an eigenvalue of zero is obtained with a probability of
. The remaining values are
with a probability of
and
with a probability of
. The fluctuations of
are given by
Here too, an extremal value is obtained for the low probability outcome. This time the fluctuation is up towards an outcome value greater than one.
The lowest average value is that of
, with only
. Similar to the statistics of
f, there are only two possible outcome values of
in the context
. A value of
is obtained with a probability of
and a value of
is obtained with a probability of
. The fluctuations are
Here, the effect of the context on the fluctuations is opposite to that observed for f. Since the low probability result 3 and the high probability result 2 have the same value, the probabilities for the two possible values are very similar. Due to this absence of rare events, the fluctuations are almost equally distributed over the different outcomes. Even the negative value of is closer to the average of than the eigenvalue of 1 obtained in the eigencontext.
The relations between different measurement contexts used for quantum state reconstructions cannot be interpreted by statistical arguments alone. Pure states represent deterministic conditions that can be used to identify contextual values for unobserved outcomes by combining each measurement outcome with the initial conditions represented by the quantum state. Weak values describe this deterministic relation between measurement contexts, explaining in detail how each measurement resolves the uncertainties of measurement outcomes from different contexts in a consistent manner. Inequality violations and quantum paradoxes can all be explained as a natural consequence of this well-defined dependence of physical properties on the specific measurement context.