Preprint
Article

Robin’s Criterion on Divisibility (II)

Altmetrics

Downloads

109

Views

119

Comments

0

This version is not peer-reviewed

Submitted:

23 October 2024

Posted:

25 October 2024

Read the latest preprint version here

Alerts
Abstract
The Riemann hypothesis, renowned for its deep connection to the distribution of prime numbers, remains a central problem in mathematics. Understanding the distribution of primes is crucial for developing efficient algorithms and advancing our knowledge of number theory. The Riemann hypothesis is the assertion that all non-trivial zeros are complex numbers with real part $\frac{1}{2}$. It is considered by many to be the most important unsolved problem in pure mathematics. Several equivalent formulations of the Riemann hypothesis exist. Robin's criterion for the Riemann hypothesis is based on an inequality that divisor sum function $\sigma$ must satisfy at natural numbers greater than 5040. We require the properties of superabundant numbers, that is to say left to right maxima of $n \mapsto \frac{\sigma(n)}{n}$. By using Robin's criterion on superabundant numbers, we present a novel approach that culminates in a complete proof of the Riemann hypothesis. This work is an expansion and refinement of the article "Robin's criterion on divisibility", published in The Ramanujan Journal.
Keywords: 
Subject: Computer Science and Mathematics  -   Algebra and Number Theory

MSC:  Primary 11M26; Secondary 11A41, 11A25

1. Introduction

The Riemann hypothesis (RH), concerning the nontrivial zeros of the Riemann zeta function, has been dubbed the “Holy Grail of Mathematics” by many [1,2]. Numerous equivalent formulations exist [3]. One of interest here is Robin’s criterion [4], which states that if RH is true, then the inequality
σ ( n ) < e γ · n · log log n
holds for all n > 5040 . Here, γ 0.57721 is the Euler-Mascheroni constant, σ is the divisor sum function, log is the natural logarithm, and n is a natural number. The superabundant and colossally abundant numbers were discovered by Ramanujan [5] and studied later by Alaoglu and Erdos [6]. The falsity of the Riemann hypothesis would imply the existence of infinitely many counterexamples to Robin’s inequality, including superabundant numbers exceeding 5040. Therefore, demonstrating the non-existence of these counterexamples would be enough to verify the Riemann hypothesis. Indeed, this is precisely what we demonstrate in this manuscript. Without a doubt, we provide a solution to this problem grounded in the properties of superabundant numbers and Robin’s criterion.

2. Background and Ancillary Results

In mathematics, the Euler-Mascheroni constant, denoted by γ 0.57721 , is defined as
γ = lim n H n log n ,
where log represents the natural logarithm and H n = k = 1 n 1 k is the n t h harmonic number. As usual σ ( n ) is the divisor sum function of n:
d n d
where d n means the integer d divides n. We define the abundancy index I : N Q with I ( n ) = σ ( n ) n . A precise formula for I ( n ) can be derived from its multiplicity:
Proposition 2.1. 
Let n = i = 1 r p i a i be the prime factorization of n, where p 1 < < p r are distinct prime numbers and a 1 , , a r are positive integers. Then [7, Lemma 1(2) pp. 2]:
I ( n ) = i = 1 r p i p i 1 · i = 1 r 1 1 p i a i + 1 = i = 1 r I ( p i a i ) .
Proposition 2.2. 
For n > 1 [8, (2.7) pp. 362]:
I ( n ) < p n p p 1 .
Definition 2.3. 
We say that Robin ( n ) holds provided that
I ( n ) < e γ · log log n .
The Chebyshev function θ ( x ) is defined as
θ ( x ) = p x log p
where the sum is taken over all prime numbers p less than or equal to x. The following inequality holds for the Chebyshev function:
Proposition 2.4. 
For x 7232121212 [9, Lemma 2.7 (4) pp. 19]:
θ ( x ) 1 0.01 log 3 ( x ) · x .
Proposition 2.5. 
For x 2278382 [9, Lemma 2.7 (5) pp. 19]:
p x p p 1 e γ · ( log x ) · 1 + 0.2 log 3 ( x ) .
Ramanujan’s Theorem asserts that the Riemann hypothesis implies Robin ( n ) for sufficiently large n [5]. Moreover, Robin’s Theorem establishes a stronger result:
Proposition 2.6. 
Robin ( n ) holds for all natural numbers n > 5040 if and only if the Riemann hypothesis is true [4, Theorem 1 pp. 188].
Ramanujan’s unpublished notes from 1997 presented generalized highly composite numbers, which encompass both superabundant and colossally abundant numbers [5]. These numbers were also explored by Alaoglu and Erdos in 1944 [6]. Given the first k consecutive primes p 1 = 2 , p 2 = 3 , , p k , an integer of the form i = 1 k p i a i with a 1 a 2 a k 0 is termed an Hardy-Ramanujan integer [8]. A natural number n is classified as superabundant if, for all natural numbers m < n , the inequality I ( m ) < I ( n ) holds.
Proposition 2.7. 
If n is superabundant, then n is an Hardy-Ramanujan integer [6, Theorem 1 pp. 450].
Proposition 2.8. 
Let n be a superabundant number. Denoting its largest prime factor by p, we have [6, Theorem 7 pp. 454]:
p log n , ( n ) .
A number n is said to be colossally abundant if, for some ϵ > 0 ,
σ ( n ) n 1 + ϵ σ ( m ) m 1 + ϵ for ( m > 1 ) .
Superabundant and colossally abundant numbers are closely related.
Proposition 2.9. 
Every colossally abundant number is superabundant [6, pp. 455].
Several analogues of the Riemann hypothesis have been proven. Many researchers anticipate or hope that the original hypothesis is true. However, there are potential consequences if the Riemann hypothesis were false.
Proposition 2.10. 
If n > 5040 is the smallest integer such that Robin ( n ) does not hold, then p > e 31.018189471 where p is the largest prime factor of n [10, Theorem 4.2 pp. 748].
Proposition 2.11. 
If the Riemann hypothesis is false, then there exist infinitely many colossally abundant numbers n > 5040 such that Robin ( n ) does not hold [4, Proposition 1 pp. 204].
By combining these results, we present a proof of the Riemann hypothesis.

3. Main Result

Definition 3.1. 
The p adic order of an integer n is the exponent of the highest power of the prime number p that divides n. It is denoted ν p ( n ) .
These are significant findings.
Lemma 3.2. 
For any superabundant number n with largest prime factor p, we have p q ν q ( n ) + 1 for all primes q satisfying 2 q p .
Proof. 
Suppose p > q ν q ( n ) + 1 . We evaluate I ( s ) for s = n and s = m = n · q ν q ( n ) + 1 p . Given the multiplicative property of I ( s ) , we focus on distinct factors. Moreover, n is superabundant and m < n . By Proposition 2.1, we obtain:
1 < I ( n ) I ( m ) = q 2 · ν q ( n ) + 2 q ν q ( n ) + 1 q 2 · ν q ( n ) + 2 1 · 1 + 1 p = 1 1 + 1 q ν q ( n ) + 1 · 1 + 1 p .
Therefore, 1 q ν q ( n ) + 1 < 1 p , implying p < q ν q ( n ) + 1 , contradicting our initial assumption. Clearly, we can observe that
q 2 · ν q ( n ) + 2 q ν q ( n ) + 1 q 2 · ν q ( n ) + 2 1 = 1 q ν q ( n ) + 1 1 q 2 · ν q ( n ) + 2 1 = 1 q ν q ( n ) + 1 1 ( q ν q ( n ) + 1 1 ) · ( q ν q ( n ) + 1 + 1 ) = 1 1 ( q ν q ( n ) + 1 + 1 ) = q ν q ( n ) + 1 ( q ν q ( n ) + 1 + 1 ) = 1 1 + 1 q ν q ( n ) + 1 .
Lemma 3.3. 
If n is a superabundant number and p is a fixed prime, then ν p ( n ) increases without bound as n grows larger.
Proof. 
By joining Proposition 2.8 and Lemma 3.2, we obtain the present result. □
The following simple observations will be used as ancillary results.
Lemma 3.4. 
If the Riemann hypothesis is false, then there exist infinitely many superabundant numbers n such that Robin ( n ) does not hold.
Proof. 
This follows directly from Propositions 2.6, 2.9, and 2.11. □
Definition 3.5. 
For each prime number p k > 2 , we define the sequence
Y k = e 0.2 log 2 ( p k ) ( 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) ) .
Lemma 3.6. 
Given that Y k is strictly decreasing, we can verify that Y k < 1.00021 whenever p k > e 31.018189471 .
Proof. 
This Lemma is straightforward. □
The following is a crucial Lemma.
Lemma 3.7. 
Consider the first k consecutive primes p 1 , p 2 , , p k such that p 1 < p 2 < < p k and p k > 7232121212 . It follows that
i = 1 k p i p i 1 e γ · log Y k · θ ( p k ) .
Proof. 
Proposition 2.4 implies that
θ ( p k ) 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) · p k .
Therefore, it is possible to prove that
log Y k · θ ( p k ) log Y k · 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) · p k = log p k + log Y k · 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) .
Thus, we can demonstrate that
log Y k · 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) = log e 0.2 log 2 ( p k ) 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) · 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) = log e 0.2 log 2 ( p k ) = 0.2 log 2 ( p k ) .
Consequently, we can establish that
log p k + log Y k · 1 0.01 log 3 ( p k ) log p k + 0.2 log 2 ( p k ) .
According to Proposition 2.5, we can show that
i = 1 k p i p i 1 e γ · log p k + 0.2 log 2 ( p k ) e γ · log Y k · θ ( p k )
when p k > 7232121212 . □
This is a main insight.
Lemma 3.8. 
For every possible superabundant number n > 5040 violating Robin ( n ) , we have
( N k ) Y k > n
where p k is the largest prime factor of n and N k = s = 1 k p s is the primorial number of order k.
Proof. 
Suppose that Robin ( n ) does not hold. Let n = i = 1 k p i a i be an Hardy-Ramanujan integer, where the primes p 1 < < p k are the first k consecutive primes, p k > e 31.018189471 and a 1 a 2 a k 0 : This follows directly from Propositions 2.7 and 2.10. Given our assumption, we can conclude that
I ( n ) e γ · log log n .
Additionally, we can infer that
p p k p p 1 e γ · log log ( ( N k ) Y k )
for all p k > e 31.018189471 , as per Lemma 3.7 with log ( ( N k ) Y k ) = Y k · θ ( p k ) . By combining Proposition 2.2 with the inequalities (1) and (2), we obtain the following result:
e γ · log log ( ( N k ) Y k ) p p k p p 1 > I ( n ) e γ · log log n .
This leads to ( N k ) Y k > n by transitivity. □
This is the main Theorem.
Theorem 3.9. 
The Riemann hypothesis is true.
Proof. 
We use a proof by contradiction, assuming that the Riemann hypothesis is not true. Given Lemma 3.4, there are infinitely many superabundant numbers n that do not satisfy Robin ( n ) . Let n k i be the infinite sequence of superabundant numbers where Robin ( n k i ) is false and p k i is the largest prime factor of n k i . Proposition 2.10 additionally implies that p k i > e 31.018189471 for all i. Equivalently, Lemma 3.6 implies that Y k i < 1.00021 . By Lemma 3.3, we conclude that there exists a finite, increasing subsequence n k j of m superabundant numbers, taken from the general sequence n k i , such that
j = 1 m log n k j j = 1 m log N k j 1.00021 ,
where N k j = s = 1 k j p s is the primorial number of order k j . Lemma 3.3 guarantees the existence of this subsequence of superabundant numbers n k j that can be made arbitrarily long, because for every fixed prime p, ν p ( n k j ) approaches infinity as n k j grows larger. Let n k 1 be the smallest element in this subsequence. Therefore, by Lemmas 3.6 and 3.8, it suffices to show that the inequality
j = 1 m log n k j j = 1 m log N k j > Y k 1
is a contradiction since 1.00021 > Y k 1 . Definitely, that’s the same as saying
j = 1 m log n k j > Y k 1 · j = 1 m log N k j
and it is clear that
Y k 1 · j = 1 m log N k j = j = 1 m log ( N k j ) Y k 1 > j = 1 m log ( N k j ) Y k j > j = 1 m log n k j
due to the fact that Y k j decreases as the subsequence n k j grows, and ( N k j ) Y k j > n k j according to Lemmas 3.6 and 3.8. Hence, our initial assumption has been contradicted. This proof by contradiction, combined with Proposition 2.6, establishes the truth of the Riemann hypothesis. □

References

  1. Conrey, B. Riemann’s hypothesis. In Colloquium De Giorgi 2013 and 2014; Publications of the Scuola Normale Superiore ((COLLOQUIASNS,volume 5)), Scuola Normale Superiore; 2015; pp. 109–117. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Connes, A. An Essay on the Riemann Hypothesis. In Open Problems in Mathematics; 2016; pp. 225–257. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Conrey, B. The Riemann Hypothesis. Notices of the AMS 2003, 50, 341–353. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Robin, G. Grandes valeurs de la fonction somme des diviseurs et hypothèse de Riemann. J. Math. pures appl 1984, 63, 187–213. [Google Scholar]
  5. Nicolas, J.L.; Robin, G. Highly Composite Numbers by Srinivasa Ramanujan. The Ramanujan Journal 1997, 1, 119–153. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Alaoglu, L.; Erdos, P. On Highly Composite and Similar Numbers. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 1944, 56, 448–469. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Hertlein, A. Robin’s Inequality for New Families of Integers. Integers 2018, 18. [Google Scholar]
  8. Choie, Y.; Lichiardopol, N.; Moree, P.; Solé, P. On Robin’s criterion for the Riemann hypothesis. Journal de Théorie des Nombres de Bordeaux 2007, 19, 357–372. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Aoudjit, S.; Berkane, D.; Dusart, P. On Robin’s criterion for the Riemann Hypothesis. Notes on Number Theory and Discrete Mathematics 2021, 27, 15–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Vega, F. Robin’s criterion on divisibility. The Ramanujan Journal 2022, 59, 745–755. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.
Copyright: This open access article is published under a Creative Commons CC BY 4.0 license, which permit the free download, distribution, and reuse, provided that the author and preprint are cited in any reuse.
Prerpints.org logo

Preprints.org is a free preprint server supported by MDPI in Basel, Switzerland.

Subscribe

© 2024 MDPI (Basel, Switzerland) unless otherwise stated