1. Introduction
Probabilities are usually defined over Boolean algebras. In the finite case, it is sufficient to give the values for the atoms. We show here that it is possible to generalize them to Heyting algebras, starting from the prime filters, in other words on the spectrum of the algebra. Surprisingly, it is also possible to define them in a quantum manner, using projectors.
2. Affine Measures
We place ourselves in a finite Heyting algebra
. The set of its filters will be denoted
and the subset of its prime filters
, which is the co-spectrum of
1. The finiteness of the algebra implies that all filters are principal.
G will be the subset of prime filter infs. A filter can be seen as a set of propositions validated at a certain time, or as the intension of a formal object.
Definition
An
affine measure on
is an application
that verifies
If, in addition, we have
,
and
, it becomes a
probability.
Let
. It is useful to introduce a deviation matrix translating relation (i) with Kronecker indices:
We can see that the affine measures verify
2, i.e.
.
Let be the matrix of the order relation of .
Demonstration
The relation on the left is , or .
If is prime, we have , and .
Apart from the trivial cases
, let’s look at the various possibilities:
And if , we find and the relation is false.
qed
Let’s denote by the restriction of the order relation to G. The strict order implies that . Let and . We see easily that . is therefore invertible. The matrix is then of rank and all affine measures are obtained by (summation restricted to G). Suppose is a classical probability on G. Since the elements of O and are positive or zero, the growth of is guaranteed. For , the sum is empty, i.e. zero, and if the sum is total and equals 1.
The result is
Theorem
Any probability is of the form
where
is a classical probability on the set
G, i.e.
.
3. Antichains
It is also possible to express these probabilities using the antichains of the algebra.
Demonstration
is the set of maximal elements of . This is an antichain, since none of these maxima is comparable to any other.
If , the antichain is empty, and we have = 0. If , we get the definition of on prime filter infs. For other elements, the ensures that are not counted more than once.
qed
Notes
The probability is first defined on G, which is generally much smaller than . It is extended to the other elements by the sum of its values on the antichains of G.
Let’s denote the antichains of
G by
. An order relation is defined by
This order makes it a distributive lattice isomorphic to
, via
4. Projectors
Let be a Hilbert space of dimension and be the set of its orthogonal projectors. If , let be the projector on the subspace generated by the union of their images, and that on their intersection. We also introduce a natural order relation given by .
We know that if , then and .
Let be an orthonormal basis of and be the associated projectors. The latter commutate and verify exactly (i).
Hence the
Theorem
Let
be given by
J is a monomorphism of distributive lattices.
Any probability on
can be written as
where
is a vector of norm 1, in other words a
amplitude of probability in the quantum sense.
Notes
If we denote by the coordinates of in the basis, we obtain .
Generally speaking, we don’t have . Better still, if , we can easily show that , , , and .
5. Conditioning vs. Quantum Reduction
The notion of
conditional probability can be traced back to the classical definition:
Theorem
Let , then
The demonstration is obvious, given the commutativity of the projectors.
is a quantum reduction operator. It is unitary, but not linear.
6. Integration and Differentiation
Since is a classical probability on G, we can introduce random variables and calculate integrals as . But is invertible, and we get . This expression uses only the values of on G. appears as a differentiation operator. This confirms that is in fact a cumulative probability.
7. Discussion
7.1. Commutative Windows
The set of projectors
with connectors
is a commutative subalgebra of
. It is a classical window on a quantum space in the sense of
Isham-Doering [
1], a context in the sense of
Kochen-Specker [
2]. The above theorems open a door to quantum modeling based on intuitionistic logic.
7.2. Square Roots
The introduction of the probability amplitude as a square root is closely related to the search for non-informative
a priori in Bayesian statistical decision theory. For example, if the aim of a sequence of experiments is to estimate a probability
by realization frequencies
, we can define, thanks to the
Fisher information, an
a priori of
Jeffreys which has interesting invariance properties [
3]. This
a priori has a density on the simplex of dimension
. The vector
has quadratic norm 1, and the density image by
is the
uniform measure [
4] on the sphere
.
7.3. Non Commutative Extension
The basis can be replaced by a partition of the identity , where the are orthogonal projectors of a Hilbert of sufficient dimension. Such a partition can be, for example, that of the eigenprojectors of a Hermitian operator whose eigenvalues are arbitrary, provided they are distinct for distinct projectors. This allows the coexistence of several operators that may only commute on certain subspaces, i.e. the coexistence of algebras for which the inter-algebra conjunction (∧) is only defined under certain conditions.
7.4. Superpositions
The non-prime filters
f of
also qualify as validating systems of propositions, but they admit disjunctions that have the following property
These disjunctions, which we might call
floating, are related to
superpositions of quantum states. In Kripke’s semantics for intuitionistic logic, these filters are not among the admissible worlds [
5].
7.5. Boole Algebras
When the algebra is Boolean, we retrieve classical probability because all prime filters are ultrafilters.
7.6. Stone Representation
The idea of replacing atoms by prime filters is obviously directly inspired by the famous Stone representation theorem.
7.7. Similarities
The linking of prime filters, projectors and G antichains emerges from the following considerations:
If the intersection of two prime filters is prime, one is in the other.
If two orthogonal projectors commute, either they are orthogonal, or one is less than the other.
If the union of two maximal antichains is an antichain, one is in the other.
7.8. Code
All these results have been confirmed by computer. The code is written in
C++, and the matrix calculations are performed by the
eigen3 library. [
6]
8. Example
These notions have been implemented and used to present
Figure 1,
Figure 2,
Figure 3 and
Figure 4. The Heyting algebra is obtained by the antichains of an arbitrary ordered set G, and the probability
by a uniform random draw of the probability amplitude
.
Notes
1 |
The term spectrum is usually reserved for ideals. |
2 |
We’ll also use index notation with Einstein’s summation convention. Here, we would have . |
References
- Doering, A., Isham, C. What is a Thing?: Topos Theory in the Foundations of Physics. Preprint at https://arxiv.org/abs/0803.0417 (2008).
- Wikipedia: The Kochen-Specker Theorem. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kochen-Specker_theorem (2024).
- Bernardo, J.M., Smith, A.F.M. Bayesian Theory. John Wiley and Sons LTD, Chichester (2000).
- Laedermann, J.-P. Sur l’estimation des répartitions discrètes. Unpublished (2005).
- Wikipedia: Semantics of intuitionistic logic. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kripke_semantics (2024).
- Eigen Eigen 3. https://eigen.tuxfamily.org/index.php?title=Main_Page (2024).
|
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).